ES: Think: Introduction In the Think Introduction the author, Simon Blackburn , attempts to provide us with a brief overview of the contents of the the novel. He also gives a base explanation for philosophy and its foundations. Blackburn begins by explaining the main purpose of the book. He wants both men and women to be able to understand “big themes”. These are subjects such as autonomy, certitudes, and morality. Blackburn believes that by reading this text, if done correctly, the audience will have a clear understanding of these “big themes” and be quite able digest complicated philosophy texts at their leisure. (Blackburn 1) I believe that Blackburn accomplishes his goal. Blackburn then continues this introduction by creating a familiarity with the reader. This will set the tone for the following text. He is not talking at the audience, but rather conversing with them. Blackburn forges this familiarity by placing himself on the level of the reader, in this case “philosophers and philosophy students” (Blackburn 2). He states that they share an instant of “silent embarrassment” when a person naively inquires as to their occupation or area of study. Blackburn then offers the description “conceptual engineering” as a possible response. He elaborates by indicating that this is what philosopher are, the engineers of logical …show more content…
thought. He then explains that, like engineers, philosophers attempt to comprehend the various components of logical thought, and with these investigations predict the outcomes or “structures”. Blackburn goes onto say that the book can be utilized on its own or with additional text. Either way, following the readers completion of the book , the reader should be sufficiently prepared to exam classic philosophical literature. In the ensuing sections Blackburn produces several examples of philosophical questions. He separates them into categories such as “questions any of us might ask about ourselves”, “questions about the world”, and “questions about ourselves and the world”. Blackburn uses these rhetorical example questions as an inception into his next point. These are not queries that can be answered by the usual systems. The aren’t questions of known mathematics or established science. In short, the are not “empirical” or questions of defined logic (Blackburn 3). They entail some deliberation. There aren’t neon signs that state “the answer is over here” and, as Blackburn suggests, the difficulty in locating these answer might stem from a lack of recognized procedures for finding them. Perhaps philosophers are unsure of where to even start looking and what would indicate that they found the answers (Blackburn 4). From where do philosophers glean these bemusing queries? Blackburn believes that they are born of “self-reflection” (Blackburn 4). Blackburn uses this string of rhetorical questions and exposition provide a snapshot as to what will be examined in the book.
In this introduction he continues to reference back to the analogy between philosophy and engineering. Blackburn uses this technique to provide a visual which is easy to understand, thereby expanding his audience past that of the seasoned philosopher. He expands on this technique by emphasizing on the base simplicity of philosophy, Socrates being his primary example:“Socrates...did not pride himself on how much he knew. On the contrary, he prided himself on being the only one who knew how little he knew.” (Blackburn
5) The author follows this by attempting to justify the study of philosophy. He does this by pointing out that if we want to place a high value on our “physical health”, then why not do the same for our “emotional health”. Blackburn is not naive and quickly acknowledges the shortfalls of this “ pure-minded reply” (Blackburn 6). He offers that the stated argument, serves mainly to preach to the choir. He then supplies a “middle-ground reply”, one which effectively states that philosophy is not a dead-end study. Blackburn goes on to give supporting examples. He sights Western philosophers, Copernicus, and instances within medical science. (Blackburn 10) His final answer is “low-ground”(Blackburn 10). This reply examines the idea that they use philosophy to “step back” and check their own beliefs against those of others, or reevaluate their legitimacy (11). For this, Blackburn uses Goya as an example. He concludes this speculation with the notion that individuals opposed to philosophy, often do so because of their own insecurities. By highlighting this fact, he utilizes a reverse-psychology which implies that a rejection of philosophy is an acceptance of ignorance. Blackburn concludes his argument with the following statement: “ It is only when we can see our situation steadily and see it whole that we can start to think what to do about it.” (Blackburn 12) This precisely supports the study of philosophy and, by extension, the reading of this book. I feel that in this Introduction to Think, Blackburn adequately persuades the reader to the notion that philosophy is an important factor in the human experience, and the following text will be beneficial in the understanding of it. He provides numerous examples and supports evidence without losing the reader in lofty diction or complex theories.
While discussing the unknown frontier that scientists must endure, Barry describes a “wilderness region” that is unfamiliar and new. He continues to say that scientists venture “through the looking glass” into a new frontier. These devices help to create familiar ideas that the audience will understand in an unfamiliar situation. A simile used to compare research to a “crystal” by explaining that “probing” was to “ precipitate an order out of chaos,” much like a crystalline structure forms an ordered structure. Finally, Berry implements a metaphor in order to describe what follows a discovery. He describes “a flood of colleagues” that “ pave roads over the path laid.” This metaphor describes how science continuously changes, one discovery after another while ultimately communicating the patience and curiosity a scientist must have. The culmination of these figurative devices teach a new way of an audience that is unfamiliar with the author's theme.
8. Paul Arthur Schilpp, as noted in Steven J. Bartlett's ``Philosophy as Ideology'', Metaphilosophy, Vol. 17, No. 1, Jan. 1986, pp. 1ff. This article is a penetrating critique of the closed-mindedness of philosophers.
of them the idea of the philosopher and he wants to see it generated as
In the essay “Thought” by Louis H. Sullivan, he states that people don’t always need words just to communicate. There are several ways that individuals are able to communicate without words, they can express themselves by gestures and facial features, like explaining themselves to others. Sullivan believes that both thinking and creative thinking are better without words and that the minds is always working; therefore, it does not have time to place words together. In order to think clearly they must use other means of pondering; although, the mind works quickly it will take a long time to write what they are thinking because the mind continues without stopping. When individuals are reading they are not think their own thought exactly but what
(*note to reader:I hope this gives all of you struggling with some concepts in Intro to Philosophy a clearer view on how to approach your own paper, please do not plagerise)
Is it possible for human beings to rise above the sensory interpretation about the world and become an intellectual? Both Plato’s “The Allegory of the Cave” and René Descartes’ “Cogito, Ergo Sum” examine this issue, and come to the conclusion that it is possible, and from this ascent, to become certain and rational. For each author, though, this is accomplished in different ways. Plato’s allegory points out that we need to look beyond the surface of the knowledge we learn and let the idea of good be our basis in life. Descartes expresses that we need to eliminate doubt in order for us to know certainty and feel comfortable in our knowledge.
John Locke's, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding (1690), was first criticized by the philosopher and theologian, John Norris of Bemerton, in his "Cursory Reflections upon a Book Call'd, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding," and appended to his Christian Blessedness or Discourses upon the Beatitudes (1690). Norris's criticisms of Locke prompted three replies, which were only posthumously published. Locke has been viewed, historically, as the winner of this debate; however, new evidence has emerged which suggests that Norris's argument against the foundation of knowledge in sense-perception that the Essay advocated was a valid and worthy critique, which Locke did, in fact, take rather seriously. Charlotte Johnston's "Locke's Examination of Malebranche and John Norris" (1958), has been widely accepted as conclusively showing that Locke's replies were not philosophical, but rather personal in origin; her essay, however, overlooks critical facts that undermine her subjective analysis of Locke's stance in relation to Norris's criticisms of the Essay. This paper provides those facts, revealing the philosophical—not personal—impetus for Locke's replies.
Moore, Brooke Noel., and Kenneth Bruder. "Chapter 6- The Rise of Metaphysics and Epistemology; Chapter 9- The Pragmatic and Analytic Traditions; Chapter 7- The Eighteenth and Nineteenth Centuries." Philosophy: the Power of Ideas. New York, NY: McGraw-Hill, 2011. Print.
Ideology is a way of thinking that reflect the social needs and political doctrines of an individual or group. There are many different people and different circumstances this results in a variety of different ways of thinking, values and beliefs. Our ideology grows with us from childhood. From the moment you are born the family influence begins to impact your thought process.
Philosophy is an ever-growing field of study due to the fact that people are constantly yearning to discover the underlying truth in all of life’s matters. Dating back all the way to before the life of Jesus Christ, a great Greek philosopher by the name of Plato, exemplified this nature. He earnestly sought to find the root of true knowledge by using the Divided Line. Plato laid a strong foundation for the future of philosophy and since his time other intelligent philosophers have arose. In the seventeenth century two of the most vital philosophers in all of history came on the scene, René Descartes and John Locke. In attempt to discover how one acquires true knowledge, these two philosophers developed extensive concepts and ideas that greatly
Garner, Richard. The Experience of Philosophy. Ed. Daniel Kolak, Raymond Martin. Belmont California: Wadsworth Publishing Company, 1996.
By calling philosophy “edifying,” Rorty calls for a more historicistic and pluralistic point of view of reality. In line with historicism, Rorty wants people to view discussions in light of the time period in which those discussions took place; he wants to see how different time periods influence thought rather than pinpointing any fundamentals truth beyond all time periods. Philosophy of the current time will serve to edify since this time period is different from other time periods and will influence thought in a new way. In line with pluralism, Rorty does not want philosophers to agree on fundamentals truths, but wants philosophers to keep interpreting the world in different ways and reach new conclusions. Rorty wants philosophers to edify by breaking away from tradition and avoiding dogma.
Alan Turing exhibits the characteristics of a genius, evidence of this comes from his description as a "math prodigy" at Kings College- Cambridge, and the fact that he became a fellow at Cambridge at the age of twenty-four. However, Alan Turing compares himself to genius's such as Newton and Einstein and believes that he is no prodigy because he has yet to accomplish as much as the two. Additionally, Turing recognizes he is one of the best mathematicians in the world, at only twenty-seven years old. Turing exhibits the characteristics of an isolated individual as seen through his inability to understand humor, his arrogance towards others, and his refusal to work as a team while trying to break Enigma, one of the greatest encryption devices
The word Philosophy comes from the Greek words of ‘philo’ meaning love and ‘sophos’ meaning wisdom (Philosophy). It is the pursuit for wisdom, to comprehend human behavior, nature and ultimately the meaning of life. Plato was the student of Socrates, influenced by his work, Plato aged to become a great philosopher himself; establishing his philosophy from that of his teacher. Aristotle was the student of Plato, and like his teacher, grew up to ground his philosophy from that of Plato. Although, both Plato and Aristotle criticized their teacher’s works, they were also influenced by them. Both Plato and Aristotle developed their own modes of knowledge acquisition; Plato’s Platonic Idealism and Aristotle’s Analytic Empiricism. In this paper, my objective is to identify the differences in the philosophy of Plato and Aristotle, which lead to the development of two contradictory modes of knowledge acquisition and their influence on succeeding thinkers.
"Local thinking" involves some "imagination, charity, and forbearance," as well as willing to be "independent and self-sufficient" (Berry, IV). "Local thinking" involves imagination because it takes creativity to separate oneself from the global culture of today and "learn to live at home," which requires independence and self-sufficiency (Berry, V). Self-efficiency will require people to live with only what the land provides and to use imagination in order to solve problems that occur with living simply (Berry, V). For example, cities should become sustainable by exchanging the massive amounts of money cities receive for fresh crops that the countryside provides; therefore, cities would be able to support local communities and use less material and the countryside could be given more money to make fresh food and not have to worry about being below the poverty line because of the just wages are given by the local communities rather than global ones (Berry, VI). Ecological good sense is another example of "local thinking" that requires the support and labor of the local communities to be independent and self-sufficient (Berry, XIV). "Local thinking" is a tight-knit community effort that requires a love for the land they live on and the love for their neighbors (Berry, XXI).