Wait a second!
More handpicked essays just for you.
More handpicked essays just for you.
How can identity impact the way someone feels about themselves
Don’t take our word for it - see why 10 million students trust us with their essay needs.
There has been a growing trend among philosophers to consider consciousness as being a strictly material phenomenon with no transcendent characteristics. Consciousness is, to those who subscribe to this school of thought, merely the effect of matter and energy interacting. This trend owes its origin to the recent advancement of neuroscience coupled with certain philosophical trends. Though neuroscience has provided many answers to ancient questions about the mind, it cannot explain the source of consciousness. The philosophical trends are, much like the appeals to neuroscience, also flawed. This philosophical camp, which will henceforth be referred to as materialists, has much popularity, but cannot explain a highly important phenomenon that …show more content…
It is an incredibly common phenomenon, something so common that it is rarely ever defined. Michael Tye, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, states that when an individual experiences something with the senses, he is “the subject of a mental state with a very distinctive subjective character” (“Qualia”). Color, taste, mood, and sound are all considered to be qualia, according to Tye. He also elucidates the standard definition of qualia, stating that it is “the introspectively accessible, phenomenal aspects of our mental lives.” Qualia is experienced only subjectively, and it is essentially impossible to say what it is. Tye references a thought experiment about the exact nature of qualia that makes this clear; one can know all objective knowledge about a color, but until one actually sees a color, one knows nothing of it. The essence of the thought experiment can be expressed in this rhetorical question: is it possible to explain what a color is without using examples? This seems like a simple question, but it boggles the mind. We must conclude that qualia is a strange …show more content…
Eliminative Materialists believe that “the concept of mental events forms part of a theory we use to interpret and apply our experience” (Freeman 94). Therefore, they would claim that qualia is merely a theory we use. But, how does this explain qualia away? Whether it is a mental construct or not, it still seems to exist. An eliminative materialist may be able to claim that qualia is merely an illusion, but this is ultimately of no importance. An illusion of qualia is still qualia. Such of a claim would be merely the addition of another layer, so to speak, in a theory of the mind. It can reasonably be concluded that any attempt to explain qualia away is incoherent at best, and begging the question at worst. The failure of Strong Eliminative Materialism, along with the failure of Reductive Materialism, means that Weak Eliminative Materialism suffers from the worst of both
The original thought experiment did not mention that science has advanced far enough to be able to explain the qualia of colour. Nor did it mention that Mary is able to imagine what it is like to experience colour vision. So, the knowledge argument argues that even though Mary does know all of the facts of colour vision; because, Mary does not know the experience of colour, physicalism must be false (pg. 35). However, this argument is flawed because it seems to be based off of ignorance (pg. 36). It is possible for Mary to have never seen red, but still know what it would look like (pg. 36). My argument is that if physicalism is more likely to be able to explain the qualia of colour than property dualism, then physicalism must be possible and more plausible than property dualism. If physicalism is possible, then someone like Mary could possibly exist in the future and know everything about colour vision, including the qualia of colour, without directly experiencing it (pg. 35). Someone like Mary in the future could possibly know everything about colour vision (pg. 36). Therefore, physicalism could possibly be true. If the
Jackson’s Knowledge Argument, while relying on the validity of epiphenomenalism, manages to stand to arguments of physicalism. The ability of conceivable ‘zombies’ to register qualia without experiencing it responds to the claims of acquaintance arguments. Furthermore, beliefs that qualia would provoke physical changes and reactions are accompanied by flawed assertions of attempting to capture the nature of causation. Qualia and the necessity of non-physical knowledge to their existence provide valid arguments to upholding dualist beliefs.
Our five senses –sight, hearing, smell, taste and touch help the ways in which we perceive the world around us. And while they seem to work independently at time they can effect each other and the way we comprehend something. Seeing something pretty, touching something soft, eating something cold and smelling something rotten are the sense we use to connect with the world around us and will all effect how we move forward in that situation. When you look at the top picture say the color of the word not the word itself. It is harder than it seems and takes a little practice to do it efficiently. It is because we see the spelling we were taught not the color it was written in. It is hard to process it the other way, but not impossible. Take the bottom picture for another example is this a
U.T. Place and J.J.C. Smart defend the view that a sensation state is a type of brain process. The ‘Sensation-Brain Process Identity Theory’ states: For any type of sensation state S, there is a type of brain state B such that: S = B. For Place, conscious experience is nothing but a brain process. Place and Smart argue against the view that acceptance of inner processes entails dualism (Place 44). Instead they hold conscious qualities can effectively be reduced to physical processes which are conscious states. A sensation state is an inner process. Inner processes according to Place and Smart are nothing ‘over and above’ brain processes. Under their view, the experience one has when tasting vanilla is the same thing as the object undergoing the corresponding type of brain process. The ‘Brain Process Identity Theory’ argues the ‘feel’ we associate with exposure of vanilla to the tongue is identical to a type of brain process cause by said exposure. To postulate non-physical properties to explain conscious states would bear the burden of proof.
The 'mind-body' problem has troubled philosophers for centuries. This is because no human being has been able to sufficiently explain how the mind actually works and how this mind relates to the body - most importantly to the brain. If this were not true then there would not be such heated debates on the subject. No one objects to the notion that the Earth revolves around the sun because it is empirical fact. However, there is no current explanation on the mind that can be accepted as fact. In 'What is it like to be a bat?', Thomas Nagel does not attempt to solve this 'problem'. Instead, he attempts to reject the reductionist views with his argument on subjectivity. He examines the difficulties of the mind-body problem by investigating the conscious experience of an organism, which is usually ignored by the reductionists. Unfortunately, his arguments contain some flaws but they do shed some light as to why the physicalist view may never be able to solve the mind-body problem.
Webster dictionary defines synaesthesia as “a subjective sensation or image of a sense other than the one being stimulated” (Wyld,1963). Synaesthesia is a condition that causes someone to have associations of usually color with certain everyday things, such as numbers or letters. There are several different types of synaesthesia that will be discussed in this paper digit-color synaesthesia, odor-color synaesthesia, and person- and music-color synaesthesia. A common effect that is discussed when talking about synaesthesia is the McCollough effect. This effect is a wonder of humans and their visual perception where colorless gratings appear to have a color.
The 21st Century has established foundations that are conducive to diving deeper in brain science and explain more of the neurological processes that occur in humans. The amount of material that neuroscience and brain science have both discovered is mind-boggling and is continuing to develop. Furthermore, physicalism argues that the mind is physical and because it is a physical form, interaction is capable of occurring between the mind and body. This theory is supported by numerous facts, but best supported the law of conservation of energy. Interactionists claim that the mind is nonphysical and believe that near-death visions can account for the spiritual mind, but our mind has become adept at imagining scenes and figures that are believed to be real. Overall, science has only been the constant evidence in any phenomena that researchers try to apprehend; therefore, physicalism is best explained through science where the mind and brain are synonymous and
To conclude this essay, I like to emphazise that Rosenthal's HOT is more of an empirical hypothesis, rather than an analysis of the term ‘consciousness.’ His aim is precisely to explain the phenomena of consciousness in relation to other mental states, such as thought and perception, and while achieving this, he has elaborated a theoretical structure for comprehending the functions of our mind.
The mind-body problem, which is still debated even today, raises the question about the relationship between the mind and the body. Theorists, such as René Descartes and Thomas Nagel, have written extensively on the problem but they have many dissenting beliefs. Descartes, a dualist, contends that the mind and body are two different substances that can exist separately. Conversely, Nagel, a dual aspect theorist, contends that the mind and body are not substances but different properties. However, although Nagel illustrates the problems with Descartes= theory, Nagel=s theory runs into the problem of panpsychism. In this paper, both arguments will be discussed to determine which, if either, side is stronger.
The desire to avoid dualism has been the driving motive behind much contemporary work on the mind-body problem. Gilbert Ryle made fun of it as the theory of 'the ghost in the machine', and various forms of behaviorism and materialism are designed to show that a place can be found for thoughts, sensations, feelings, and other mental phenomena in a purely physical world. But these theories have trouble accounting for consciousness and its subjective qualia. As the science develops and we discover facts, dualism does not seems likely to be true.
Kim, J. (1993). Supervenience and mind : selected philosophical essays. New York: Cambridge University Press.
...e to claim that objects that were created by humans, including robots, wire and metal structures and series of computer networks could and do possess qualia. Once people have reached the highest nirvana in the limits of consciousness and can create a consciousness device to measure its depths among classes of humans and non-humans, then functionalism can be shelved and rejected if it is the case that a robot does not contain qualia. Until then, however, functionalism needs to be carefully considered and not disregarded for its merits in the problem of mental states. Though for many, psychofunctionalism may be the more favorable choice because it is easier for people to consider themselves as the most intelligent beings and rulers of the universe rather than every collection of objects that satisfy the functional role to have consciousness on the same level as them.
While the great philosophical distinction between mind and body in western thought can be traced to the Greeks, it is to the influential work of René Descartes, French mathematician, philosopher, and physiologist, that we owe the first systematic account of the mind/body relationship. As the 19th century progressed, the problem of the relationship of mind to brain became ever more pressing.
While the main problem for dualism is explaining how two distinctly different properties of mind and body enter into causal relationships, the ongoing mind-body debate has spawned many more problems relating to subjective experience and free will (Hardnad, 1992; Jaworski,
perceptions that are not obvious, such as the taste of food. Colours can also enhance the