Aristotle believes there was an ultimate telos for the human; it was eudaimonia, which is to be a flourishing person. In order to reach eudaimonia, a person must choose to become a virtuous person. In a similar way, N.T. Wright believes that Jesus’ followers have a telos; however, he argues that the Christian virtue of Love is missing from Aristotle’s view and therefore a Christian that develops love will understand eudaimonia more than can be found in the Aristotelian view. In this paper, I will briefly explain Wright’s view of the Christian’s telos and then highlight the overlap of Aristotle and Wright’s understanding of developing virtue. Then I will argue in favor of Wright’s view that love will lead to a greater eudaimonia than the …show more content…
In the Aristotelian view, virtue is developed by habitually choosing to act in ways that are virtuous. A person must choose ends to become a virtuous person; a person does not choose to become temperate, it is by doing acts of temperance that a person gains that virtue (Aristotle, 504). In the same way, Wright states, “Virtue… is what happens when someone has made a thousand small choices… to do something which is good and right but which doesn’t “come naturally”— and then… that thousand and first occasion, it does indeed look as if it “just happens”... (21). They are in agreement that virtues do not just happen but must be …show more content…
I think that Wright is correct to point out this discrepancy. In the Aristotelian view, eudaimonia is the end goal; however, even a quick read of 1 Corinthians 13 reveals that Paul believed there was an undeniable connection between love and the ultimate telos. From a Christian perspective, I do not think that the absence of love is compatible with God’s new world. In supporting love as a major theme of Christianity, the third century Church Father Cyprian quoted 1 Corinthians 13:8 and declared, ‘It will exist forever in the kingdom, it will endure forever in the union of the brethren among themselves…. Christ, who said, “This is my commandment, that you love one another as I have loved you” (Ramsey, 1904). It is only with an understanding of God’s love that the gospel speaks into the world, Paul writes in Romans, “But God demonstrates His own love toward us, in that while we were yet sinners, Christ died for us” (5:8 NASB). It is in the context of the Father’s love that Dr. Enns cites this verse as evidence pointing us to who is the object of the Father’s love (7568). Therefore, I believe that Wright is correct in saying that the Aristotelian view of becoming a virtuous person is very self-centered, even
Franklin and Aristotle both agree that one can’t simply adopt virtue by force of will. However, Franklin believes that a virtue can be established by making it a habit through one’s actions; whereas, Aristotle believes that virtue is innately established in one’s nature. Franklin describes his definition of virtue when he says “...contrary habits must be broken, and good ones acquired and established, before we can have any dependence on a steady, uniform rectitude of conduct” (Franklin). Franklin writes about how to possess virtue and how actions establish a habitude of virtue. This differs from Aristotle’s views due to his belief that actions result from nature, not habit. He illustrates this when he says “Actions, then are called just and
Ogien defines “character broadly speaking, [as] a certain way of acting or feeling that is consistent, that is, stable over time and unvarying from one situation to the next” (Ogien 123). For Aristotle, “virtue, is a state of character concerned with choice, lying in a mean…relative to us, this being determined by…that principle by which the man of practical wisdom would determine…and acquired by repetition” (Aristotle 124, 129). Mark Timmons, a moral philosopher, also makes a slight distinction between character and virtue by defining virtue as “(1) a relatively fixed trait of character (2) typically involving dispositions to think, feel, and act in certain ways in certain circumstance, and (3) is a primary basis for judging the overall moral goodness or worth of persons” (Timmons 212). Additionally, bioethicists Tom Beauchamp and James Childress define virtue in terms of “a trait of character that is socially valuable and a moral virtue [as] a trait of character that is morally valuable” (Beauchamp 31). My reason for going through the ways in which different philosophers have defined virtue is to (1) show that Ogien critiques virtue ethics without correctly representing the term virtue in the theory or defining virtue at all and (2) to show that among moral philosophers (at least read for this week) there is commonality in defining virtue in some way or another as a fixed character. (3) Just because a person possesses a certain character trait that does not mean that that person is virtuous and (4) in regard to the Milgram experiments, there is no way to determine the virtuous character of the subjects involved based solely on this one experiment alone. Virtuous character requires consistency of a particular character trait. Virtue is not a one-time act or an act on occasion. From the point-of-view of virtue ethics, we can only “take as a sign of states of character the pleasure or
Eudaimonia is a Greek word often translated into English as “happiness” or “flourishing.” Thus, Aristotle wouldn’t say that the goal of eudaimonia is happiness, but rather that eduaimonia just is happiness (the trick, then, for this paper
The meaning of eudaimonia, etymologically, is ‘good spirit’ and it is generally translated as ‘happiness’; in Aristotelian terms, ‘happiness’ represents the highest human good and it is also the representation of the soul’s virtues. The identification of the soul parts as the contributors and main elements for the function of the most important human activity (reasoning), marks the inevitable psychological asset of Aristotle’s thinking; specifically, the classification of human virtues derives from the analysis of the soul’s types, attributing to human beings the ability of reasoning which distinguishes human beings from the rest of ‘natural bodies.’ Indeed, reason exists in two parts of the soul, namely the rational and the appetitive (desires or passions), and so it expresses within two different virtues, the moral and intellectual ones.
In the Symposium, a most interesting view on love and soul mates are provided by one of the characters, Aristophanes. In the speech of Aristophanes, he says that there is basically a type of love that connects people. Aristophanes begins his description of love by telling the tale of how love began. He presents the tale of three sexes: male, female, and a combination of both. These three distinct sexes represented one’s soul. These souls split in half, creating a mirror image of each one of them. Aristophanes describes love as the search for the other half of your soul in this quote: “When a man’s natural form was split in two, each half went round looking for its other half. They put their arms around one another, and embraced each other, in their desire to grow together again. Aristophanes theme is the power of Eros and how not to abuse it.
Ethical virtues deal with actions of courage, generosity, and moderation. Intellectual virtues deal with wisdom and contemplation. Ethical virtues are created through habitual actions. Aristotle says that humans are not born with a natural capacity for virtue. He believes that education and cultivation as youth by one’s parents are pivotal in setting up humans’ ability to make virtuous acts habitual.
There are several aspects to consider when exploring the Christian worldview. There are many facets or denominations and they each have their own distinct beliefs and practices, but they all share the same fundamental beliefs. In this Paper we will explore the character of God, His creation, humanity and its nature, Jesus’ significance to the world, and the restoration of humanity, as well as my beliefs and the way that I interact with Christianity and my personal worldview.
He claims that virtue of thought is taught and that virtue of character is habitually learnt. Either way, virtues do not “arise in us naturally” (216, 1103a20). He argues that humans have the capacities for virtues, but they must act on them (216, 1103a30). Thus, a person must learn to use the capability of being virtuous, meaning someone needs to teach them those virtues (217, 1103a10). To be virtuous, it is not just the action that matters, but the reason behind the action too. Aristotle says that a person should be consciously acting virtuous because this would result in him living a happy life (221, 1105a30). This takes time and a person must constantly repeat these actions to achieve the end goal of being virtuous (221,
Aristotle, argued that he could not judge a person on the basis of one example and wanted to look at the whole over time. Additionally he argued virtue was found between the extremes of each characteristic. Balance between the extremes of emotion was his main concern (Manning and Stroud 59). Virtue ethics requires one to strive for excellence, a process that happens over a long period of time. It includes learning about ethics, struggling with them, and eventually living ethically (Class
Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics provided a valuable framework based on his theories of achieving happiness and which life is the most worthy of fulfilling in life. One of his foundational beliefs in his system of beliefs is that happiness can be achieved on an individual level with the embracement of virtue. Determining what the virtue is, there exists two vices that set parameters as excessive or deficient, and what is in between is considered the virtue, or ‘mean state’, for which one should relate towards when using “good reason” to make an action. The ‘Doctrine of the Mean’ explains that a virtue is a mean between excessive and deficient, and the doctrine’s intentions were to push one towards achieving Eudaimonia, a Greek phrase that roughly
As it is alluded to in the Euthyphro, the concept of piety is one in which all followers of faith and beyond strive to understand and adhere to the manifestation of. For hundreds of years after this dialogue the question of piety and divine command still alludes the wisest thinkers and holiest of men. Is the pious being loved by the gods because it is pious, or is it pious because it is being loved by the gods? With only two paths to venture down, both having unpleasant results, this question is still unanswered to most. But the importance of the question remains. To question everything we encounter, to question everything we think we already know, and to “prefer nothing, unless it is true (14e)”. In this essay I will argue that the Gods commanding good actions because they are already good is the
Aristotle states within the Nicomachean Ethics that there are two kinds of virtue, intellect and character. "Intellectual virtue owes its origin and development mainly to teaching for which reason its attainment requires experience and time; virtue of character is a result of habituation, for which reason it has acquired its name through a small variation on "ethos"" (Nicomachean Ethics,1103b). This statement explains that our opportunity to be virtuous is given to us through our personal circumstances. That we obtain virtues by exercising them. Throught habituation we become more virtuous, "similarity with courage: by becoming habituated to make light of what is fearful and to face up to it, we become courageous; and when we are, we shall be most able to face up to it" (Nicomachean Ethics, 1104b).
We obtain virtue by practicing it. However, if we do not practice it correctly (the right thing, the right way, the right amount, at the right time, and for the right reason), the virtue is destroyed. For it is in doing it incorrectly that we are practicing not the virtue, but the vice. Think of the example already used: courage. If we face fear with a healthy amount of courage, we become courageous.
When considering morality, worthy to note first is that similar to Christian ethics, morality also embodies a specifically Christian distinction. Studying a master theologian such as St. Thomas Aquinas and gathering modern perspectives from James Keenan, S. J. and David Cloutier serve to build a foundation of the high goal of Christian morality. Morality is a primary goal of the faith community, because it is the vehicle for reaching human fulfillment and happiness. Therefore, great value can be placed on foundations of Christian morality such as the breakdown of law from Aquinas, the cultivation of virtues, the role of conscience in achieving morality, and the subject of sin described by Keenan.