Wait a second!
More handpicked essays just for you.
More handpicked essays just for you.
Morality and the human condition
Morality and the human condition
Concept of moral responsibility
Don’t take our word for it - see why 10 million students trust us with their essay needs.
Recommended: Morality and the human condition
My goal in this essay is to show that Tooley’s response to the Potentiality Argument (that is, the argument formulated in the essay question) is not successful and that the fetus ' potential for a valuable life and future does morally justify extending to it a right to life. I begin with a formulation of the Potentiality Argument. Next, I present Tooley’s response to this argument. Finally, I argue that this response fails to establish the claim that killing a person and letting a person die both have an equal moral standpoint.
The Potentiality Argument can be formulated as follows. If A (any being, human or nonhuman) has a potential for personhood and a valuable life, then it is morally impermissible to kill it. A fetus/infant has the
…show more content…
He poses a hypothetical situation in which newborn kittens are injected with a serum that would allow them to develop, later on, the mental capabilities required for becoming a sentient person with self-concept and self-awareness. Since a kitten will eventually develop human like capabilities, then it follows that it is now a potential person. In this case, Tooley states that it would be unjustifiable not to reward cats the same right to life as members of the species Homo sapiens. Following this, Tooley integrates this hypothetical situation with his moral symmetry principle to establish that the distinction between action and inaction lacks moral significance, provided both cases have the same motivation. In other words, killing a person and letting a person die both have an equal moral standpoint. The principle is illustrated in the following example from the text. “(1) Jones sees that Smith will be killed by a bomb unless he warns him. Jones 's re- action is: "How lucky, it will save me the trouble of killing Smith my- self." So Jones allows Smith to be killed by the bomb, even though he could easily have warned him. (2) Jones wants Smith dead, and there- fore shoots him” (Tooley, p. 59). In …show more content…
Tooley’s claim that killing a person and letting a person die both have an equal moral standpoint is erroneous, as intentionally killing a person worsens an individual 's situation and makes you play an active role in his/her death, whereas refraining from saving a person from dying, in some cases, will not make you play an active role in his/her death. For example, let’s imagine one of your friends, A, is lying in a small hospital with person B and they ran out of oxygen tanks. You arrive at the hospital with one oxygen tank. If you give the oxygen tank to A, then B dies. In this case, you are not playing an active role in B’s death. If, on the other hand, B happens to have an oxygen tank and you detach it from him/her and give it to A, then this follows that B will die. In this case, you are playing an active role in the death of B. This example, as a result, addresses my concerns surrounding Tooley’s moral symmetry principle and shows that a moral difference does in fact exist when it comes to killing a person or refraining from saving
Patrick Lee and Robert P. George’s, “The Wrong of Abortion” is a contentious composition that argues the choice of abortion is objectively unethical. Throughout their composition, Lee and George use credibility and reason to appeal the immorality of abortions. The use of these two methods of persuasion are effective and compels the reader to consider the ethical significance. Lee and George construct their argument by disputing different theories that would justify abortions. They challenge the ontological and evaluation theories of the fetus, as well as the unintentional killing theory. This article was obtained through Google, in the form of a PDF file that is associated with Iowa State University.
In this essay, I will argue that though Strawson’s Basic Argument is sound, society has constructed a more applicable version of the term “acting morally responsible” which holds us all accountable for our actions. Firstly, I will provide a brief overview of the Basic Argument as well as distinguish between Strawson’s and society’s definitions of being morally responsible. Secondly, I will justify Strawson’s first premise. Finally, I will raise and refute the response of author Ian McEwan.
Thomson starts off her paper by explaining the general premises that a fetus is a person at conception and all persons have the right to life. One of the main premises that Thomson focuses on is the idea that a fetus’ right to life is greater than the mother’s use of her body. Although she believes these premises are arguable, she allows the premises to further her explanation of why abortion could be
Marquis’ argues that like adult humans, fetuses have the ability to experience a future and by preventing them from experiencing that future through abortion is the same as killing an adult human.
“I intend to judge things for myself; to judge wrongly, I think, is more honorable than not to judge at all.” What author Henry James meant by this was that it is better to make up one’s mind and have an opinion than to remain complacent, such as the case of Mary Anne Warren. Warren’s arguments for abortion’s possible permissibility are lacking in substance. The aim of my paper is to discuss Warren’s insufficient criteria for personhood and address the problem with her concept of potential personhood. “I argue that it is personhood, and not genetic humanity, which is the fundamental basis for membership in the moral community” (Warren 166).
Consequentialism is ordinarily distinct from deontology, as deontology offers rightness or wrongness of an act, rather than the outcome of the action. In this essay we are going to explore the differences of consequentialism and deontology and apply them to the quandary that Bernard Williams and J.J.C Smart put forward in their original analogy of “Jim and the Indians” in their book , Utilitarianism: for and against (J.J.C Smart & Bernard Williams, 1973, p.78-79.).
In the article 'A Defense of Abortion' Judith Jarvis Thomson argues that abortion is morally permissible even if the fetus is considered a person. In this paper I will give a fairly detailed description of Thomson main arguments for abortion. In particular I will take a close look at her famous 'violinist' argument. Following will be objections to the argumentative story focused on the reasoning that one person's right to life outweighs another person's right to autonomy. Then appropriate responses to these objections. Concluding the paper I will argue that Thomson's 'violinist' argument supporting the idea of a mother's right to autonomy outweighing a fetus' right to life does not make abortion permissible.
In the essay “Gentle Murderer, or the Adverbial Samaritan” James William Forrester attempts to solve the contradictory statements of the Forrester’s Paradox. According to Forrester, readers ought to imagine a “... legal system which forbids all kinds of murder, but which considers murdering violently to be a worse crime than murdering gently” (Forrester, 194). This imagined legal system has two rules to which its citizens must abide. First, it is obligatory that one does not commit an act of murder. The second rules states that if one does commit an act of murder, it is obligatory that he or she does so gently. These two rules are the introduction of the contradiction in Forrester’s Paradox, and the explanation of each premise will show the contradiction in this paradox. The following is a summation of Forrester’s Paradox.
Mary Anne Warren’s “On the Moral and Legal Status of Abortion” describes her justification that abortion is not a fundamentally wrong action for a mother to undertake. By forming a distinction between being genetically human and being a fully developed “person” and member of the “moral community” that encompasses humanity, Warren argues that it must be proven that fetuses are human beings in the morally relevant sense in order for their termination to be considered morally wrong. Warren’s rationale of defining moral personhood as showcasing a combination of five qualities such as “consciousness, reasoning, self-motivated activity, capacity of communication, and self-awareness” forms the basis of her argument that a fetus displays none of these elements that would justify its classification as a person and member of the morally relevant community (Timmons 386).
But, arguing against this point, since a fetus does not have a desire to live, or any desires at all for that matter, then it is not wrong to kill the fetus. To backup this argument, David Boonin states in his book, A Defense of Abortion, “Since the pre conscious fetus is not conscious, it does not have ideal desires in this sense. And so, on this account, the best account of why you and I and temporarily comatose adults and suicidal teenagers have a right to life does not imply that the pre conscious fetus
A considerable difference is that Marquis’ beliefs are associated with the uncertainty of the future whereas Tooley’s beliefs are invested in the present. Tooley claims that because a fetus isn 't a fully capable person, a fetus is not afforded a merit in a decision such an abortion. Tooley’s argument is based solely on what the fetus is capable of before birth. Marquis’ argument is based on potential following birth. Marquis holds the value of a human future to a high regard. Marquis makes a profound point when he compares the refusal to kill suicidal teens to the anti-abortion position. He emphasizes that the reasoning for not killing suicidal teens is solely because the teen could possibly posses “the desire at some future time to live.” Thus, simply because one is not capable of desiring life does not mean one is not worthy of
Many arguments in the abortion debate assume that the morality of abortion depends upon the moral status of the foetus. While I regard the moral status of the foetus as important, it is not the central issue that determines the moral justifiability of abortion. The foetus may be awarded a level of moral status, nevertheless, such status does not result in the prescription of a set moral judgement. As with many morally significant issues, there are competing interests and a variety of possible outcomes that need to be considered when making a moral judgement on abortion. While we need to determine the moral status of the foetus in order to establish the type of entity we are dealing with, it does not, however, exist in a moral vacuum. There are other key issues requiring attention, such as the moral status and interests of the pregnant woman who may desire an abortion, and importantly, the likely consequences of aborting or not aborting a particular foetus. Furthermore, I assert that moral status should be awarded as a matter of degree, based upon the capacities of sentience and self-consciousness an entity possesses. In a bid to reach a coherent conclusion on the issue, the moral status of both foetus and woman, along with the likely results of aborting a particular foetus, must be considered together. Given the multiple facets requiring consideration, I assert that utilitarianism (Mill 1863) offers a coherent framework for weighing and comparing the inputs across a variety of situations, which can determine whether it is ever morally justifiable to have an abortion.
The goal of this paper is to examine John Harris’ experiment of the “Survival Lottery.” Specifically, I want to argue that the lottery makes too high a demand on us to give up our lives. Especially, when I’m pretty sure everyone wants to live. Prior accounts show that Harris proposes that if the argument of the distinction between “killing” and “letting die” is properly contrived, then killing one person to save two could happen on a regular basis. It would be an exception to the obligation not to kill innocent people in regards to the argument that there is a distinction between "killing" and "letting die.” The difference between killing and letting die presents a moral difference. As far as this argument we are obligated not to kill. I
... which the act is done does matter to them. Utilitarianism is very vulnerable in this regard. A case where some people’s happiness is created at the cost of a few may not always be ethical. Opposition may say that “Someone always is left out in this theory” but I argue that this is always the case.
People who believe we are not morally obligated to save the drowning child typically argue that the dichotomy of right and wrong eliminates non-moral acts. It would be noble if someone saved the child of their own volition. If someone did not do so because they thought they had better things to do, no one could compel them to save the child; it wouldn 't be wrong, but morally neutral, like not getting out of your car to move a bag of trash off the highway. If this “morally neutral” category didn 't exist, we would treat the ignorance and inaction of every single individual at all possible moments to not prevent suffering as the same as malicious action. Would we really want to penalize someone because they could have saved the life of a child halfway across the world from them if they gave them some money, but chose instead to spend money on tickets to a movie theater? Say a mother stops feeding her child and lets this child starve to death. Is this an immoral act or a morally neutral act? Both in this case and the drowning child case, the child is in a position where they are helpless to avoid death on their own, and so they are reliant on someone else to save them. In this case, the mother is not specifically undertaking an act of murdering her child. She is not metaphorically "throwing her child into the pond," but rather she is just being purposefully negligent in a way that will result in her child 's death, just as a person is when avoiding saving a drowning child. The only way out of calling this a morally neutral act is to say that the mother has an obligation as a mother to save her child. This is precisely the point of Singer’s argument: we have an obligation as a global society to assist the people who are helpless to save themselves. Is a parent obligated to save a child from downing? Is a child obligated to save a parent? Is a sibling