Wait a second!
More handpicked essays just for you.
More handpicked essays just for you.
Empiricism and rationalism
A brief summary on rationalism vs empiricism
Empiricism and rationalism
Don’t take our word for it - see why 10 million students trust us with their essay needs.
Recommended: Empiricism and rationalism
Immanuel Kant’s Epistemology
Eighteenth Century Europe was in turmoil, “characterized by dramatic revolutions in science, philosophy, society and politics” (Bristow, 2011, para. 1). Revolution was afoot in France, while earlier scientific discoveries from Copernicus to Newton drastically changed how humans understood the world. Empiricism and Skepticism rose with modern science to challenge the prevailing Rationalism (Murphy, 2010).
The grand and complex debate that emerged between Continental Rationalists, the likes of Renee Descartes and Gottfried Wilhelm von Leibniz, and British Empiricists, such as John Locke and David Hume, epistemologically hinged on the notion of whether there is knowledge beyond experience. More specifically, the debate
…show more content…
revolved around whether one could have knowledge beyond empirical experience, and therefore how much one can know with certainty (Markie, 2015). At this juncture it is significant to distinguish between the types of knowledge. Knowledge that is a priori is “objective” and based on pure reason, with “all truths necessary truths that cannot be false” (Seung, 2007). The long-standing Rationalist belief held that knowledge is a priori, sourced from beyond direct experience, from what can be described as reason, logic. In essence, “theoretical, conjecture, or belief” (Seung, 2007, pp. 3). Empiricists, on the other hand, significantly influenced by the rise of modern science, maintained that knowledge can result only from direct empirical experience, or sense experience as it is often referred to, and is thus a posteriori, as in empirical or “known to be validated” (Dudley, 2011, pp. 19). “Reason may inform the relationship of ideas,” according to Empiricists, but it cannot generate knowledge (cite). Whereas Rationalists maintained all truths are knowable, Empiricists conversely held it impossible to have absolute certainty what is true (Dudley, 2011). This is, admittedly, a simplification of the debate as it stood in the 1700’s. As it happens, philosophers have often accepted and rejected bits and pieces of their own and opposing philosophies, making it inaccurate to suggest a strict dividing line could be drawn between the camps. Nevertheless, these are the core concepts behind the Rationalist – Empiricist debate as encountered by Immanuel Kant (1724-1804), a well-respected professor and Rationalist in the Liebnezian tradition, who by account lived a happy and successful existence in Konigsberg, Prussia (cite). In 1770, already in his forties, Kant took a position as professor of philosophy at the University of Konigsberg (Jankowiak, 1. Life, para. 2), up until this time, “fully enmeshed in the German rationalist tradition” (Jankowiak, a. pre-critical phase, para. 1) shaped by Gottfried Leibniz and Wolff. Kant was concerned over the growing sense that “everything can be explained in terms of science and mechanical laws” (podcast?), which threatened his belief in that which is beyond knowable, for Kant this chiefly faith and free will (cite podcast). It was in this atmosphere of uncertainty that Kant encountered the writings of Empiricist David Hume. Hume’s theory of knowledge posits all knowledge is either analytic a priori or synthetic a posteriori (Stearns, 2013). For Hume, analytic a priori knowledge is “independent or experience” or simply “mere thinking” (Stearns, 2013). Analytic a priori truths are universal and necessary, or “true by definition” (Moore, 2008), for example all bachelors are single men or 2 + 2 = 4 (Stearns, 2013). The other prong of Hume’s Fork, as the theory is named, is synthetic a posteriori knowledge, which is derived from direct sense experience, or that which we would need to validate by empirical measures (Stearns, 2013; Moore, 2008). Rationalists and Empiricists agreed that knowledge exists as analytic a priori and synthetic a posteriori, but Hume asserted that all judgement is a posteriori to reinforce his view that “facts about that world cannot be known by reason alone” (cite). This directly challenged Kant, who until this point had “devoted himself to…reconciling the metaphysical claims of Rationalists with empirical science” (cite). For Kant, who believed “we can know things about the empirical world without basing this knowledge on experience” (Moore, 2008?), this comes too close to questioning the principles of the Enlightenment itself. Kant thus concludes “all analytic knowledge is a priori, but some synthetic knowledge cannot be a posteriori” (Moore, 2008), thereby creating a third prong for Hume’s Fork. Analytic a priori knowledge can be described as true by definition or meaning, in that the subject is contained in the predicate, for example the previous statement “All bachelors are unmarried men” (cite). In Kant’s opinion, this could not translate to “7 + 5 = 12” (Dudley) or “between two points you can only have one straight line” (Moore, 2008), neither of which are “known by definition...[nor] require direct experience” to be known (Moore, 2008). With Kant’s proposition of synthetic a priori knowledge, that which is based on pure reason alone, his pre-critical stage comes to a close as he rejects his own Rationalism and Hume’s phenomenalism.
With the idea of synthetic a priori knowledge as the springboard, Kant develops his critical philosophy, rejecting his own direct realism as well as Hume’s more radical Empiricist views (Seung, 2011). The Critique of Pure Reason (1778) is Kant’s seminal epistemological work, in which he outlines his “grand theory of perception,” which he termed transcendental (Seung, 2011, pp. 1). Kant’s transcendental philosophy provided a new way of understanding knowledge, and expanded our ideas of what we can know, how we know, and the limits to what we can …show more content…
know. Seung (2011) summarizes Kant’s theory of knowledge by identifying knowledge as that which “requires intellect in addition to sensibility” (pp. 3). Intellect provides us concepts, or thoughts, while sensibility provides awareness or intuition, and together these form a judgement, the “basic unit of knowledge” (Seung, 2011, pp. 3). Judgements can be a prior or a posteriori, analytic or synthetic, but only together can concepts and sensibility combine to result in knowledge (Seung, 2011, pp. 3). Kant believed our ideas begin with empirical a posteriori perception but evolve into intuitive a priori knowledge (Seung, 2011). In the Critique of Pure Reason (1778) Kant strove to give structure to knowledge-making in arguing some truths are known only through pure reason, in the process giving rise to what we now refer to as human cognition.
In Kant’s view, human cognition or intellect, is comprised of sensibility and understanding. For Kant, sense perception is either a priori or a posteriori, the former being innate and intuitive, framed by space and time not in the physical but perceptual sense, while the latter is direct sense perception and empirical in nature (Seung, 2011). Understanding, in Kant’s philosophy, utilizes categories to structure and order thought in knowledge-making. According to Heidemann (2011) “categories are simply logical functions of judgements, but determinations of [a priori] intuitions” (pp.
54). Kant explains reality in terms of phenomena and noumena (Seung, 2011). The phenomenal world is the knowable world, the synthetic a priori realm through which we can know reality as pure concepts (e.g. science, math, things). Conversely, the noumenal world is that which is “inaccessible or unknowable” (Seung, 2011, pp. 22). Here Kant set definite limits to what we can know, which is not everything. One of Kant’s most significant moves was to reclassify metaphysical knowledge as transcendental, effectively making it synthetic a priori and within the phenomenal, knowable world. Equally groundbreaking was Kant’s perception of reality itself. The common perception in the Eighteenth Century was that the mind imposed reality on the world, meaning each individual’s reality might be different. Kant flipped this idea, asserting that “reality conforms to the structures of the mind, rather than the other way around” (Moore, 2008). To Kant, we all experience the same reality; we simply perceive our reality individually. This reversal in thinking, not unlike that of Copernicus with our universe, was dubbed Kant’s Copernican Revolution (cite). In Kant’s view, reality is simply our perception of what we know to be true, but it is impossible to know the true nature of the world (Moore, 2008). Kant uses the metaphor of spectacles to illustrate his idea of perception. Time and space, for example, are the temporal-spatial lens through which we perceive and make sense of our innate sense perceptions (cite). Kant called his theory of perception Transcendental Idealism. Legacy/Implications/Applications Kant would later write two additional critiques, focused more on moral, ethical, political, and aesthetic theories, while the Critique of Pure Reason remains his greatest contribution to epistemic thought. Kant’s transcendental philosophy effectively brought an end to Continental Rationalism on the basis of synthetic a priori knowledge upset and effectively brought an end to Continental Rationalism. Rise of German Idealism. Established metaphysics as a legitimate discipline. Copernican Revolution’s as foundational for the advancement of scientific knowledge. Influence on the philosophy of math, physics, and science. Cognitive science. Longevity of transcendental idealism. Rise of theoretical science, through Darwin’s Origin of the Species, Einstein’s Theory of Relativity, and quantum mechanics, all theoretical in nature and unknowable by pure logic, discredited a prior knowledge from possibility, though the debate continues between today’s rationalists and empiricists. Even more so than in Kant’s time, one could find their philosophy rational in the realm of mathematics and empirical in the realm of the hard sciences. When Kant died in 1804 he did not receive the understated funeral of his request, but a state funeral fit for a dignitary (Schaub, 1924). Even in his own era Kant’s contributions to philosophical thought were well recognized. Although some may have been disqualified over the intervening 211 years, his transcendental philosophy continues to be the focus of scholarly research, actively debated, and applied in the modern context, marking his timeless contributions to epistemology.
In the sixteenth and seventeenth century a Scientific Revolution swept over Europe. The start of this Scientific Revolution has been atributed to Nicolaus Copernicus and his Heliocentric Model of the Universe.
Immanuel Kant is one of the renowned representatives of German modern philosophy which was predominantly built on the philosophical concepts of human right, mind, morals and the importance of ownership. His central concept is reason and philosophical epistemology is based not only on theoretical, but also combined with the empirical aspects, which refers to the practical philosophy that covers from human behavior to human action. Generally speaking, the practical philosophy deals with the ground concept that relates to the human deliberative action. In the “Critique of Pure Reason” says that there is only congenital right, the independence which is the right to be detached from the other’s interest. Kant’s
Accepting that we cannot establish the "objectivity" of our experiences' content, Kant nevertheless attempts to resist a slide into relativism by insisting that they are mediated by rationally delineated categories which supposedly insure the transcendental or universal nature of their form, thereby providing an absolute standard against which we might check the veridicality of our descriptions of, and communications concerning, them. However as a priori preconditions of the possibility of experience such categories are obviously inexperienceable in themselves, and consequently must also fall to the phenomenological reduction. (3) Nevertheless, a moments reflection will confirm that our experiences do indeed exhibit structure or form, and that we are able, even from within, or wholly upon the basis of, the (phenomenologically reduced) realm of, our experiences per se, to distinguish between the flux of constantly changing and interrupted subjective appearances, and the relatively unchanging and continuously existing objects constituted therein. Husserl confirms:
Noumena are the things themselves, which compose reality. Kant argues that objects conform to the mind rather than the mind conforms to objects. The fundamental laws of nature, “are knowable precisely because they make no effort to describe the world as it really is but rather prescribe the structure of the world as we experience it” (“Kant: Experience and Reality”). This was a breakthrough in the field of epistemology. We can understand the view of the phenomenal realm by applying intuition and understanding. However, it is challenging to fully understand the noumenal realm because human knowledge is fundamentally limited in its ability to understand external
The first philosophical movement responding to the thinkers of the 17th century that will be discussed is the rationalist movement. It is generally known to be started by Descartes in the 17th century, while the torch was carried by Spinoza and then Leibniz up until his death in 1716. Two things distinguished the rationalists from their empiricist counterparts. The rationalists believed that foundational concepts of reality were found in reason, not experience. These foundational concepts are called innate ideas, and from these innate ideas the rationalists believed that one could deduce truth, much in the way geometrical proofs are thought out.
Francis Bacon and Thomas Hobbes were not truly conscious of the phenomenalistic consequences of their theory of knowledge, which was based on empiricism. Both considered sensation as phenomenal presentations and also as representations of reality. Thus they still had something upon which to build an absolute metaphysics. With Locke gnosiological phenomenalism enters its critical phase. By considering sensations merely as subjective presentations, Locke gives us a theory of knowledge of subjective data devoid of any relation with external objects. Hence Locke is the first to give us a logic for Empiricism, that is, for sensations considered as phenomena of knowledge.
The Transcendental Deductions of the pure concept of the understanding in Immanuel Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, in its most general sense, explains how concepts relate a priori to objects in virtue of the fact that the power of knowing an object through representations is known as understanding. According to Kant, the foundation of all knowledge is the self, our own consciousness because without the self, experience is not possible. The purpose of this essay is to lay out Kant’s deduction of the pure concept of understanding and show how our concepts are not just empirical, but concepts a priori. We will walk through Kant’s argument and reasoning as he uncovers each layer of understanding, eventually leading up to the conclusion mentioned above.
While Kant’s theory may seem “overly optimistic” (Johnson, 2008) now, it was ruled as acceptable and rational behavior then. Kant believed that any moral or ethical decision could be achieved with consistent behavior. While judgment was based on reason, morals were based on rational choices made by human beings (Freeman, 2000). A human’s brain is the most advanced in the animal kingdom. Not only do human beings work on instinct, but they have the ability to sort out situations in order to make a decision. This includes weighing the pros and cons of decisions that could be made and how they affect others either positively or negatively. This is called rational thought. Kant believed that any human being able to rationalize a decision before it was made had the ability to be a morally just person (Freeman, 2000). There were certain things that made the decision moral, and he called it the “Categorical Imperative” (Johnson, 2008). If someone was immoral they violated this CI and were considered irrational. The CI is said to be an automatic response which was part of Kant’s argument that all people were deserving of respect. This automatic response to rational thinking is where he is considered, now, to be “overly optimistic” (Johnson, 2008).
In what is widely considered his most important work, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Locke establishes the principles of modern Empiricism. In this book he dismisses the rationalist concept of innate ideas and argues instead that the mind is a tabula rasa. Locke believed that the mind was a tabula rasa that was marked by experience and reject the Rationalist notion that the mind could perceive some truths directly, without sensory experience. The concept of tabula
Wolf, Abraham. History of Science, Technology, and Philosophy in the Eighteenth Century. New York: MacMillan Press, 1968. Web. 5 June 2012.
Probably few philosophers influenced so decisively the development of epistemology as Kant. Without him it is not possible to describe the last two hundred years of the history of philosophy as well as contemporary philosophy in general. On the other "end of the line" one of the most influential contemporary American philosophers Richard Rorty proposes that we should abandon epistemology and Kantian picture of representation. In this paper I pose the question, whether Rorty is thorougly succesful in his abandomnent. I try to investigate the differences and similarities of Kantian and Rortyan thinking with the help of the epistemological notion of representationalism and of the antiepistemological notion of antirepresentationalism. If it is possible to find crucial overlapping areas of both thinking, then there arises a dilemma: either Kant himself is a "Rortyan", postepistemological thinker, and this would be a surprizing new idea about Kantian philosophy or Rorty succeeds not completely to overcome the structures of Kantian-epistemological thinking.
During the enlightenment era, rebellious scholars called philosophers brought new ideas on how to understand and envision the world from different views. Although, each philosopher had their own minds and ideas, they all wanted to improve society in their own unique ways. Two famous influential philosophers are Francis Bacon and John Locke. Locke who is an empiricism, he emphasizes on natural observations. Descartes being a rationalist focus more on innate reasons. However, when analyze the distinguished difference between both Locke and Descartes, it can be views towards the innate idea concepts, the logic proof god’s existence, and the inductive/deductive methods. This can be best demonstrate using the essays, “An Essay Concerning Human Understanding”
... proof than analytic a priori claims or synthetic a posteriori claims. A synthetic a priori claim adds to what is analytically contained in a concept without appealing to experience. Kant explains the possibility of a priori judgements by appealing to the mind’s role in shaping experience. According to him, by applying categories to intuition, we put what is in our minds into our experiences. The categories shape the experience and we can know that that aspect of experience is a priori since it belongs to us. “We can cognize of things a priori only what we ourselves have put into them.”
Throughout the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, radical and controversial ideas were created in what would become a time period of great advances. The Scientific Revolution began with a spark of inspiration that spread a wild fire of ideas through Europe and America. The new radical ideas affected everything that had been established and proven through religious views. "The scientific revolution was more radical and innovative than any of the political revolutions of the seventeenth century."1 All of the advances that were made during this revolutionary time can be attributed to the founders of the Scientific Revolution.
Over the course of the years, society has been reformed by new ideas of science. We learn more and more about global warming, outer space, and technology. However, this pattern of gaining knowledge did not pick up significantly until the Scientific Revolution. In the sixteenth and seventeenth century, the Scientific Revolution started, which concerned the fields of astronomy, mechanics, and medicine. These new scientists used math and observations strongly contradicting religious thought at the time, which was dependent on the Aristotelian-Ptolemy theory. However, astronomers like Copernicus, Kepler, Galileo, and Newton accepted the heliocentric theory. Astronomical findings of the Scientific Revolution disproved the fact that humans were the center of everything, ultimately causing people to question theology’s role in science and sparking the idea that people were capable of reasoning for themselves.