Wait a second!
More handpicked essays just for you.
More handpicked essays just for you.
Aristotle and happiness essay
Aristotle and happiness and virtue
Aristotle and happiness essay
Don’t take our word for it - see why 10 million students trust us with their essay needs.
Recommended: Aristotle and happiness essay
For Aristotle happiness is the criteria through which the natural goal or telos of a man is assessed (Roberts and Sutch, 2004: 51). Although the Greek word commonly translated as “happiness” is eudaimonia, it is a far more intricate concept than physical pleasure. Barnes describes Aristotle’s highest human good, eudaimonia, as ‘the activity of the soul in accordance with excellence’ (Barnes, 1982: 78). However, it begs the question as to how one becomes virtuous or excellent. In this way, there are disagreements as to what constitutes eudaimonia and the role of the political participation in order to attain it (Duvall and Dotson, 1998: 23). By establishing happiness as an inadequate translation for eudaimonia, this essay seeks to establish that happiness or eudaimonia does not entirely depend ‘upon citizenship or full membership of political society’ (Roberts and Sutch, 2004: 53).
One of the main objective of the doctrine that man is a ‘political animal’ is to demonstrate that ‘men need company of others, not only for the necessities of life but for the good life itself’ (Politics, 1, 2, 1252b30; Mulgan, 1990: 205).
The inference that it is not vital for the virtuous citizen of the polis to participate in the political activity, is confirmed by Aristotle’s account of the virtues themselves (Mulgan, 1990: 206). Excellence or virtue (arête) is a mean between two extremes which involves finding ‘the midpoint in a circle’ determined by rationality and reason of a given individual (Ethics: 2, 9, 11093a25). According to Aristotle, as humans are capable of philosophical reasoning, in order to attain happiness, the rational individual is required to assess his soul and consult with his rational friends in order to cultivate towards the...
... middle of paper ...
...quals for political rule, the theoretical possibility of absolute rule becomes a crucial part of it. This causes difficulties because if Aristotle values citizenship and political participation as vital for attaining eudaimonia, then the possibility of absolute rule is clearly inconsistent with his standard of justice as virtuous and capable citizens would have to give up their citizenship. Conversely, Aristotle would argue that surrendering citizenships can be done without loss of virtue or eudaimonia as both types of rule are equally just. Fundamentally, both provide outstanding virtuosity, ability and rule in the interest of all which is crucial for obtaining a good government and eudaimon life. Thus, even in the most just state, the value of political participation is such that it should be accepted when offered although it is not essential for the eudaimon life
... against him. With regard to the second objection, Aristotle can begin by accepting that whereas it is indeed true that the parts prior to the whole or the polis - the single associations, respectively - do not contain the virtue for the achievement of eudaimonia in themselves alone, it is through the conjunction of them all that the capacity for this virtue emerges. Indeed, the parts of the city-state are not to be taken distinctively. For instance, whereas five separate individuals alone may not have the capacity to each lift a 900 lbs piano, the five together, nonetheless, can be said to be able to accomplish this. Similarly, it is the city-state with all of its parts that can achieve the good life. In any case, it remains that humankind is essentially political since it fulfills the function of reason, and this function is best performed under the city-state.
Aristotle accepts that there is an agreement that this chief good is happiness, but that there is a disagreement with the definition of happiness. Due to this argument, men divide the good into the three prominent types of life: pleasure, political and contemplative. Most men are transfixed by pleasure; a life suitable for “beasts”. The elitist life (politics) distinguishes happiness as honour, yet this is absurd given that honour is awarded from the outside, and one’s happiness comes from one’s self. The attractive life of money-making is quickly ruled out by Aristotle since wealth is not the good man seeks, since it is only useful for the happiness of something else.
The meaning of eudaimonia, etymologically, is ‘good spirit’ and it is generally translated as ‘happiness’; in Aristotelian terms, ‘happiness’ represents the highest human good and it is also the representation of the soul’s virtues. The identification of the soul parts as the contributors and main elements for the function of the most important human activity (reasoning), marks the inevitable psychological asset of Aristotle’s thinking; specifically, the classification of human virtues derives from the analysis of the soul’s types, attributing to human beings the ability of reasoning which distinguishes human beings from the rest of ‘natural bodies.’ Indeed, reason exists in two parts of the soul, namely the rational and the appetitive (desires or passions), and so it expresses within two different virtues, the moral and intellectual ones.
In consideration to Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle’s view of the great-souled man is that of an individual that represents happiness and obtains the five virtues: wisdom, justice, bravery, self-control, and the overall goodness within an individual (happiness). The magnanimous person is very complex and displays the proper virtues at the proper time, and in the proper way. In addition, the great-souled man accommodates to his surroundings where he is honorable but not boastful in his actions. Aristotle believes that it is only possible to attain happiness within a political organization because happiness represents living well without being concerned with others, they solely live for the truth and not approval.
From examining ends and goods, Aristotle formulates eudaimonia. He questions “what is the highest of all the goods achievable in action?” (Shafer-Landau 2013, 616). Aristotle argues that the majority of people agree that the highest good is achieving happiness, however, they disagree over what happiness actually is, for example, some claim t...
Simply defined, happiness is the state of being happy. But, what exactly does it mean to “be happy?” Repeatedly, many philosophers and ideologists have proposed ideas about what happiness means and how one attains happiness. In this paper, I will argue that Aristotle’s conception of happiness is driven more in the eye of ethics than John Stuart Mill. First, looking at Mill’s unprincipled version of happiness, I will criticize the imperfections of his definition in relation to ethics. Next, I plan to identify Aristotle’s core values for happiness. According to Aristotle, happiness comes from virtue, whereas Mill believes happiness comes from pleasure and the absence of pain. Ethics are the moral principles that govern a person’s behavior which are driven by virtues - good traits of character. Thus, Aristotle focuses on three things, which I will outline in order to answer the question, “what does it mean to live a good life?” The first of which is the number one good in life is happiness. Secondly, there is a difference between moral virtues and intellectual virtues and lastly, leading a good life is a state of character. Personally and widely accepted, happiness is believed to be a true defining factor on leading a well intentioned, rational, and satisfactory life. However, it is important to note the ways in which one achieves their happiness, through the people and experiences to reach that state of being. In consequence, Aristotle’s focus on happiness presents a more arguable notion of “good character” and “rational.”
It is in light of these last two points that we shall make our way into analyzing an often neglected text of St. Thomas, the De Regno. Perhaps one of the most telling aspects of this short, incomplete work of Aquinas is that it provides a unique glance at his account of the political community and authority, and their necessity for man’s growth in moral virtue. While providing a substantial and positive account of the polis as ordered towards the common good, St. Thomas nevertheless limits its proper aim and scope on account of two reasons: virtue comes about only by degrees, and that the ultimate end of man transcends the political community. Man is made for the City of God, but this need not entail an indifference towards, or inadequate account of, political life.
One of Aristotle’s conclusions in the first book of Nicomachean Ethics is that “human good turns out to be the soul’s activity that expresses virtue”(EN 1.7.1098a17). This conclusion can be explicated with Aristotle’s definitions and reasonings concerning good, activity of soul, and excellence through virtue; all with respect to happiness.
To begin, this writer interprets Aristotle’s vision of “man is a political animal” to mean that man’s disposition is dependent on the natural order of life. “Hence it is evident that the state is a creation of nature, and that man is by nature a political animal” (Liberty Fund, Inc., 2008). That is to say, that man is an individual within the community, within the state; therefore, he is
In readings these accounts and depictions, it quickly becomes apparent that Aristotle’s characterizations and ranking of governmental forms best stands the test of time and reflects a modern view of the “ideal” form of government. While an ideal version of monarchy could very well serve as the best form of government, its inherent unsustainability means
Happiness is the goal of every human beings according to Aristotle, however what does happiness imply? It is in his attempt to define happiness and to find a way to attain it that Aristotle comes across the idea of virtue. It is thus necessary to explain the relationship between these two terms. I will start by defining the good and virtue and then clarify their close link with the argument of function, I will then go into more details in explaining the different ways in which they are closely related and finally I am going to give an account of the apparent contradiction in Book X which is a praise of the life of study.
Consequently, if indeed there are several kinds of constitution, it is clear that there cannot be a single virtue that is the virtue-of a good citizen. But the good man, we say, does express a single virtue: the complete one. Evidently, then, it is possible for someone to be a good citizen without having acquired the virtue expressed by a good man" (1276b). What Aristotle doesn't tell us is who is better off. Is it sufficient to be the good citizen or is it definitely more satisfying to be the good man? The good man is recognizably superior to the good citizen. The good man possesses everything that is good. He does what is just and what is just is beneficial to himself and to those around him. His soul is completely well-ordered and, therefore, cannot allow for his desires to take over and commit evil or injustice of any kind.
Throughout book four, Aristotle talks about what would be the best regime. As he goes on, Aristotle relates the four cardinal virtues, justice, courage, wisdom, and moderation to his explanation of the “best” regime. Aristotle is basically presenting the idea as to what characteristics the “best” regime should have in order to be fair to all citizens being governed. In the passage, Aristotle argues that in order to have the best regime, you must create a regime that is equal and fair to everyone. “Hence, agreement must first be reached on what is for everyone, practically speaking, the most choice worthy way of life, and then on whether this way of life is the same for all in common as for each separately or whether it is different” ( 1323a14,
Both Plato’s Republic and Aristotle’s Politics relegate some people to exist solely as laborers, but they come to this conclusion in different ways and for fundamentally different reasons. In the Republic, the protagonist Socrates explores the idea of justice and the question of whether or not justice manifests in the same form for the individual as for the state. Socrates believes that these qualities are wholly entwined, as both the justice of the state and the justice of the individual require a balance and embodiment of certain qualities. A good society will be “wise, courageous, [and] moderate,” and all of these qualities must exist independently (Plato 427e). In his construction of an ideal city, Socrates declares that each of these
...that happiness is not found in amusement for it is too incongruous to end in amusement, and that our efforts and sufferings would be aimed at amusing ourselves. A flourishing life—a happy life, is one that consists of numerous requirements having been fulfilled to some degree. These include those things that preserve and maintain physical welfare such as, a certain level of material wellbeing, health, satisfaction, good familial and friendship bonds, and a comely appearance. Additionally, certain intellectual and moral needs ought to be met as well. It is a well-ordered and just state and community that preserves the freedom to have such a life. Thus, eudaimonia—happiness—for Aristotle is an inclusive notion consisting of life in accordance with intellectual and moral virtues, rational contemplation, and securing certain physical needs, such that one is flourishing.