Epicurus Death Argument Analysis

1169 Words3 Pages

Epicurus’s Death argument is very simple, and thus can be hard to refute. The basic premise is that is that no one feels any pain while they are dead, thus being dead is not a painful experience, so being dead is not bad for the one who is dead. My goal for this paper is to prove how those premises fails. In section 1 I will explain in greater detail Epicurus’s argument, in section 2 I will attack those arguments citing various theoretical examples, and in section 3 I will defend my attacks against potential rebuttals.
The Epicurean Death Argument
Epicurus felt strongly about his position, as is exhibited in the following quotation:
“Become accustomed to the belief that death is nothing to us. For all good and evil consists in sensation, but …show more content…

(A2) If (1), then no one feels any pain while dead.
(A3) If no one feels any pain while dead, then being dead is not a painful experience.
(A4) If being dead is not a painful experience, then being dead is not bad for the one who is dead.
(A5) Therefore, being dead is not bad for the one who is dead.
A1 and A2 are easily granted points. Once one is dead he certainly ceases to exist and because of this feels no pain. A4 is where more of the controversy comes in. Epicurus makes a big jump by correlating pain and badness together. It can be granted that being dead is not a painful experience, but to say that because it is not painful it is not bad for the person who died is highly controversial. This is the point I will argue in the paper. A4 rests on a very faulty premise and thus A5 must be revised.
Section 2: Arguing The Epicurean Death Argument Epicurus was admittedly a Hedonist, and this philosophy has had a huge influence on his work. Especially so on his death argument. Hedonism is, “the doctrine that pleasure is the only thing that is good in itself for a person, pain the only thing that is bad in itself for a person.” …show more content…

Eating the candy is at first a very enjoyable experience. It is intrinsically good, but will cause serious pain later. Eating the candy will lead to later pain, thus eating the candy is extrinsically bad. So, it is clear that something can simultaneously be intrinsically good as well as extrinsically bad. This distinction does pertain to the Epicurean argument. It is logical and sound for an individual to believe that since being dead in itself is not a painful experience, death is not intrinsically bad. But the issue arises when it comes to extrinsic badness. To imply that pain and badness are interrelated in death, as Epicurus does, is a problem. There are many things that are extrinsically bad, such as verbal bullying or the death of a parent, that do not cause physical pain. Thus, death can be extrinsically bad despite not causing any

Open Document