Wait a second!
More handpicked essays just for you.
More handpicked essays just for you.
Virtue ethics and duty ethics
Kant theory of moral duty
Kant's ideas about duty
Don’t take our word for it - see why 10 million students trust us with their essay needs.
Recommended: Virtue ethics and duty ethics
Kant on Welfare Immanuel Kant was a German philosopher who has played a vital role in the development of modern philosophy. In his writing he discusses the duty of rational beings and what these duties entail. In his system, Kant differentiates between two duties: duties of right or juridical duties and duties of virtue or ethical duties. A duty of right is a duty that can be firmly enforced by law and by the state. A duty in which a moral agent must be constrained only inwardly by one’s own reason is a duty of virtue. Kant believes that we have no direct duties of right when it comes to non-rational nature because of the fact that only finite rational beings have enforceable rights (MS 6:241). Any duties of right that may be required of us that involve the treatment of non-rational nature must be consequent to the rights of human beings and laws made by the general will of the state. Kant touches on this by exemplifying laws promoting …show more content…
the common good or fulfilling its collective moral duties (MS 6:325-328). A prime example of this is charity toward the poor. The fact that non-rational beings have no rights does not entail that the general will of a state may not legislate restrictions on how they may be used or treated according to Kant’s theory The most basic, yet essential, division among ethical duties is between duties toward ourselves and duties toward others.
Kant fails to ever provide us with an explicit account of what it truly means for a duty to be a duty to or toward someone. But it is not hard to construct such an account. It is apparent that Kant regards only rational beings as persons and these persons are to be treated as ends. He refers to all other beings as things. Even his statement of the Formula of Humanity as End in Itself – “So act that you use humanity, whether in your own person or in the person of any other, always at the same time as an end, never merely as a means” (G 4:429) – involves the idea that humanity or rational nature has a moral claim on us only in the person of a being who actually possesses it. To paint a picture, think of it this way: Duty X is a duty toward Y if and only if Y is a rational being, and the moral requirement to obey X is grounded on the moral requirement to respect the humanity that exists withing the person of
Y. Duties to ourselves are duties mandated by the respect that we owe to our own humanity within us. Kant believes that the end of all duties to ourselves is our own natural or moral perfection. His reason for believing this is derived from the respect for humanity that we exemplify by attempting to perfect our rational nature (MS 6:385-387). If duties to ourselves require us to perform or disregard certain actions in order to evade moral blame they are referred to as strict duties. If they mandate no specific action but the actions that fulfill these duties are worthy of praise in terms of merit, then they are referred to as wide duties (MS 6:390-394).
Kant argued that the Categorical Imperative (CI) was the test for morally permissible actions. The CI states: I must act in such a way that I can will that my maxim should become a universal law. Maxims which fail to pass the CI do so because they lead to a contradiction or impossibility. Kant believes this imperative stems from the rationality of the will itself, and thus it is necessary regardless of the particular ends of an individual; the CI is an innate constituent of being a rational individual. As a result, failure ...
According to Kant “… nothing can protect us from a complete falling away from our idea of duty and preserve in the soul a well-grounded respect for duty’s law except the clear conviction that, even if there never have been actions springing from such pure source, the question at issue here is not whether this or that happened but that reason of itself and independently of all experience commands what ought to happen.” (Kant, Page 20(lines 407-412)). Kant points out that the duty is done not because of the ends but because of what is fundamentally good or
In this paper, I will critique Kantian ethic’s failure to defend beings disputably labeled “irrational.” The concept of a rational being is a common motif throughout Immanuel Kant’s “Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals.” These beings comprise the foundation of his entire argument. Therefore, for the purpose of this essay, it is crucial to further examine what is meant by “rational.” Kant offers three essential requirements that separate rational beings from their irrational counterparts; the ability to reason, a moral will, and autonomy (53, 49, 41.) Rational beings are those included in his ideal “kingdom of ends” (39.) He defines this kingdom as “a systematic union of rational beings through common objective law” (39.) Since Kant’s code of ethics only applies to those deemed rational, some fundamental questions remain ambiguous. Firstly, in what manner should Kant’s higher capacity beings interact with those “incapable” of reason? Could those who fail to meet the three requirements be abused or exploited? Would this be justified? Some may conclude that Kant has evaded these inquiries altogether.
The second act of Kant’s categorical imperative pertains to how we treat others. According to Kant, we must “Act in such a way that you always treat humanity, whether in your own person or in the person of any other, never simply as a means, but always at the same time as an
Actions of any sort, he believed, must be undertaken from a sense of duty dictated by reason, and no action performed for expediency or solely in obedience to law or custom can be regarded as moral. A moral act is an act done for the "right" reasons. Kant would argue that to make a promise for the wrong reason is not moral - you might as well not make the promise. You must have a duty code inside of you or it will not come through in your actions otherwise. Our reasoning ability will always allow us to know what our duty is.
According to Kant, rational people have to act according to the categorical imperative, which can be thought of as a sort of tool or set of rules that people can use to decide whether or not an action is genuinely morally acceptable. There are multiple formulations derived from it. The first formulation states that people should only act according to certain rules or maxims that can become universal laws that apply to everyone without contradictions. This means that in a given scenario, the situation should be generalized into a universal law. If this universal law is applied to everyone in a hypothetical world, it must make sense and be possible without contradictions. Even the hypothetical world does make sense without contradictions, it must also be a world that people would want to live in. If an action does not pass this test, Kant says that we have a perfect duty not to do that particular action ever. For example, people have a perfect duty not to lie because in a world where everyone lies, no one would ever know who was telling the truth, no one would trust anyone, and it would be a world that no rational person would want to live in. For each of these reasons, humans have a perfect duty not to lie to one another. It is also possible for certain things to be considered imperfect duties, or things that you should do some of the time but you’re not necessarily always obligated to...
Immanuel Kant is a popular modern day philosopher. He was a modest and humble man of his time. He never left his hometown, never married and never strayed from his schedule. Kant may come off as boring, while he was an introvert but he had a great amount to offer. His thoughts and concepts from the 1700s are still observed today. His most recognized work is from the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. Here Kant expresses his idea of ‘The Good Will’ and the ‘Categorical Imperative’.
Kant’s moral philosophy is built around the formal principles of ethics rather than substantive human goods. He begins by outlining the principles of reasoning that can be equally expected of all rational persons regardless of their individual desires or partial interests. It creates an ideal universal community of rational individuals who can collectively agree on the moral principles for guiding equality and autonomy. This is what forms the basis for contemporary human rig...
So, we need to look at one’s reason for doing an action to determine if it is a duty. If the reason for performing the action is justified, then the action is a duty. However, Kant says there are two different types of reasons for performing an action. Kant calls these reasons ‘imperatives.’ The first reason for performing an action, the hypothetical imperative, is based on consequences and on our personal preferences.
Kant presents his followers with both categorical and hypothetical imperatives (Reitan). The hypothetical imperatives, often dubbed the imperfect duties, basically state, “If you want X, do Y (Reitan).” In other words, hypothetical imperatives are not obligatory of people, but encourage certain actions for certain results. Categorical imperatives say, “Do Y, no matter what you want (Reitan).” These perfect duties, as they are referred to as, are rules that we must follow without any acceptable exceptions (Degrazia, Mappes and Brand-Ballard). These perfect duties include the forbidding of killing innocent people, lying, breaking promises, becoming intoxicated, committing suicide, and masturbating (Horn). Kant ultimately believes that reason dictates what is right and wrong through the categorical imperative of Kantian Deontology, which has two formulations (Reitan). The first states, “Act only on that maxim that you can at the same time (consistently) will to be a universal law (of nature) (Reitan).” This is the philosophical equivalent of “treat others the way you want to be treated.” The second formulation, which could arguably provide a different
This essay will explain the validity of Kant’s argument by first explaining Kant ’s view on duty, then analyse his view of
In this chapter I will explain Immanuel Kant concept of what is right and how the categorical imperative plays an important role in his moral philosophy.
Looking at Kant’s Theory of Divine Commands through his deontological theory, we can acknowledge that the right or wrongs of an individual’s actions does not depend on the consequences of those actions, but rather if they are fulfilling our duties. According to Interpreting Kant’s Theory of Divine Commands by Patrick Kain “Kant rejected “theological morality”, insisting that no one, including God, can be the “author” of the moral law because the more law id categorically necessary, non-positive law.” Kain continues and states “Kant repeatedly suggest (in his published works, notes, and lectures) that is proper, even necessary to view our moral obligations as divine commands. As Kant wrote in the Religion, “an ethical community is conceivable only as a people under divine
Immanuel Kant was a philosopher who made great contributions with his work on the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. Kant’s interest with metaphysics left him in the company of Aristotle, who had the original work on metaphysics. Kant’s goal in the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals was to find and make the supreme principal of morality. Kant covers several concepts in his work on metaphysics, some of the key concepts in his work are good will, moral worth, and imperatives. When it comes to good will Kant believes that “Nothing in the world—indeed nothing even beyond the world—can possibly be conceived which could be called good without qualification except a good will” 1. In the next key concept, moral worth, Kant believes that actions are only morally right depending on their motives, “an action done not from inclination but from duty” 2 is morally right according to Kant. Kant’s imperatives are broken down into two types, those being hypothetical and categorical. A hypothetical imperative is an “action that is good to some purpose, possible or actual” 3. A categorical imperative “directly commands a certain conduct without making its condition some purpose to be reached by it” 4. From these concepts you can tell that Kant is a perfect world philosopher who thinks that all humans are rational beings, who have preeminent good in them, and should always strive to be their best selves.
Immanuel Kant has a several "duty based" ethics. Another word for his belief in "duty based" is Deontological ethics. Other two theories are teleological ethics, and consequential ethics. Kant believes teleology is wrong, which put's Kant into the category of a Deontological ethicist. This is apprehensive to specifically what people do, and totally disregard the consequence of the person's actions. Some specific "duty based ethic's are , Do the right thing, do it because it's the right thing to do, don't do the wrong thing, especially avoid the wrong things because "they are wrong". Realistically you can't validate any person's action by showing that the action showed a good outcome, this is also sometimes call a "non- consequentialist". Immanuel Kant believed that "we have a duty to ourselves and to others to think beyond our own particular situation and to recognize an obligation to life itself" ( Immanuel Kant).