Wait a second!
More handpicked essays just for you.
More handpicked essays just for you.
The roles of courts in society
Don’t take our word for it - see why 10 million students trust us with their essay needs.
Recommended: The roles of courts in society
Gerald Rosenberg, Stuart Scheingold, and Charles Epp are three influential voices in the debate over law’s capacity to achieve social change. When speaking of law in this context, the authors are focused on court decisions and look to the Supreme Court for most of their case studies of interest. Although each avoids a simple “Yes, courts are effective” or “No, they are not” theory of social change, there are both overlaps and disparities among their respective claims. Not only do they fall on different points on the spectrum of whether or not courts are effective change makers, they also stress different reasons for why or why not this is this case –how court action can be meaningful for progress. Taken together, their arguments address both …show more content…
the material and cultural, or symbolic, resources that must be present in order to further progressive social change using the law. Also related is the often mythical nature of these legal rights and to what extent this myth has any bearing on reality. Rosenberg most strongly refutes claims of the courts’ efficacy for social change, as suggested by the title of his book, The Hollow Hope.
He recognizes that two prevailing views of courts’ roles are each insufficient explanations: the “dynamic court” view that the judiciary can act for the otherwise politically disadvantaged in the face of opposition and the “constrained court” view that the court is by its nature largely unable to do so. He does conclude that the latter is a more accurate description of reality. He directly relates the dynamic court view to the “myth of rights” – the belief in rights’ intrinsic existence and power – described by Scheingold. Although Scheingold also approaches rights with skepticism, he ultimately gives more weight than does Rosenberg to their power, as far as the myth itself can serve as a political resource. In his more contemporary preface, Scheingold acknowledges Rosenberg’s evidence of the impotence of the courts. However, he counts it as irrelevant to the development of a new politics of rights. Scheingold does, however, consider Epp’s work as building toward what a new iteration of the politics of rights would ideally look like. Epp’s primary claim is that support structures – which can include the provision of financial support and specifically the ability to afford legal aid – are necessary to facilitate the actual impact of formal, symbolic …show more content…
rights. The connections among the three authors go beyond their explicit attributions to one another and include the relative importance given to both material and immaterial resources in pursuing social change through legal channels. This conversation also overflows to connect with other important works in this field of study. For instance, in terms of necessary material conditions, each of their arguments in some way supports the claim of Marc Galanter that the “haves” – those with wealth and/or power – come out ahead when interacting with the law. Scheingold also notes that resources are necessary for winning the litigation game. Although Rosenberg critiques Galanter for neglecting what happens after a decision, Galanter’s classifications are in fact useful for understanding how advantages continue into the enforcement stage. Epp’s central support structure claim is about the necessity of resources in bringing actual success ¬– a rights revolution – through implementation. However, it is important to note that this support structure is only rarely created or strengthened by the courts themselves. Epp also recognizes the closely related necessity of being a “repeat player” who is able to engage in sustained litigation. Rosenberg uses Brown v. Board of Education (1954) as one of his key examples of the Court’s failure to bring about substantive change, despite the case’s reputation. However, for Epp, the achievements of Brown must be understood in the context of the cases that followed it. Large law firms and advocacy organizations bring benefits such as economies of scale that can allow for such an ongoing campaign. The NAACP-LDF, the Justice Department, and the ACLU enabled the success of the individual litigants in Monroe v. Pape (1961) and the subsequent strengthening of civil rights. Scheingold also stresses the importance of evaluating the legal success of desegregation within the larger context of the growing strength of the civil rights movement, with some of this strength coming from successful litigation itself. Rosenberg would add that both “haves” and “repeat players” are also in a better position to resist the practical impositions of formal legal progress that does not benefit them, as has been the case with large polluters and environmental protection laws. The benefit of being a have and a repeat player may extend beyond this more observable power. For example, Scheingold notes the importance of collective identities and the role that organizing and litigation can play in shaping these identities and drawing attention to shared grievances. Lawyers themselves bring not only technical expertise but also a sense of significance and gravity. A lawyer can turn an individual problem into a political one. The converse, noted elsewhere, is a lawyer’s power to act as a gatekeeper by “cooling out” legitimate problems. More generally, the conversation surrounding the ability of law to change society should recognize that change is a cultural, not simply technical, project. In Scheingold’s more recent preface, he notes that the literature on patterns of legal consciousness, such as the work of Patricia Ewick and Susan Silbey, would be informative for a new articulation of the politics of rights. Their conception of legality is closely related to his discussion of popular understandings about rights, obligations, and guilt. The decision in Brown was a statement about the political significance of the grievances regarding segregation. Scheingold’s theory recognizes that rights granted or affirmed in the courtroom can affect perceptions, which can subsequently affect reality. A significant obstacle to progressive social change is acceptance of the status quo by those suffering injustice. Although Epp is centrally concerned with the necessity of a support structure in actually giving voice to and ensuring impact of legal rights, he does also recognize the symbolic foundations underlying rights revolutions. For example, even though the formal passage of the14th Amendment itself did not have immediate effects, it did change conceptions about rights, which laid some long-dormant groundwork for the eventually rights revolution in the U.S. For Epp, popular rights consciousness alone will certainly not produce change, but it is necessary for it, largely because rights revolutions are bottom-up rather than top-down processes. Not only can court action legitimize a desire for social change, but it can also instill hope about what change is possible by sending signals about potential outcomes. Scheingold similarly discusses how validation by a court spurns future mobilization. This signaling process is documented elsewhere in regard to both formal law and law-like sets of rules. Laura Beth Nielson noted in her study of street harassment that experience with how the law responds, or fails to respond, to a harm shapes willingness to use the law in the future as a means of social change. The women in Anna-Maria Marshall’s piece also stopped bringing claims under their workplace harassment policy when they observed that they would not be taken seriously. Rosenberg does not completely negate the importance of social attitudes in helping or hindering social progress, but he does not find that court action itself plays a role in this cognition process.
In the case of civil rights, what happened in the courtroom was merely a reflection of the growing pressure outside; the court itself did not help build this pressure. Using evidence on popular attitudes, Rosenberg largely dismisses the claim of the dynamic court view that courts are “educators” able to influence the hearts and minds of society. In terms of implementation, compliance is achieved when there are tangible costs for noncompliance such as loss of federal funding or competitive edge in the
market. Rosenberg takes his critique of the symbolic victory even further. Not only are symbolic wins ineffective, but they also contribute to myths that mask inequalities. Formal rights can lure people into believing that they have fulfilled their moral obligations or serve as covers for injustice. For example, the Miranda warning and environmental protections are often used as procedural “check boxes” and hide a lack of substantive change. Neither Scheingold nor Epp is oblivious to this danger. For example, Epp tells of an early proponent of legal aid who saw it as a way to enhance the perceived fairness of the legal system and keep new immigrants from taking more radical action. Scheingold also notes that symbolic change can sometimes be wrongly confused with substantive change. Rosenberg concludes that the distant myth of rights should be sacrificed for strategic benefit. Advocates for same-sex rights would have been better off going after civil unions rather than marriage, even if marriage equality feels more symbolically meaningful. Even in the absence of backlash or pacification, Rosenberg points to limited resources as a reason for abandoning litigation to pursue other avenues of change. None of the authors proffer that courts can independently orchestrate progress – each unpacks a certain set of external conditions and constraints, to use Rosenberg’s language, that facilitate or hinder it. However, Scheingold and Epp at least offer a glimmer of hope for the role of legal rights (though Scheingold is a bit more cautious in presenting his argument in the later edition). In any case, change is likely to be incremental, largely because of the weakness of the courts in enforcement. Epp challenges critics, putting on them the burden of explaining why we should return to a pre- “rights revolution” state, before access to court became more democratic and when only the “haves” had any reason to hope.
...e to breach Supreme Court sovereignty would render the different minorities, residing in the United States, helpless to further governmental legislature justifying racial discrimination. In their struggle to preserve racial inequality segregationists immorally resorted to using violence against children. Through “a sharp realisation of the shameful discrimination directed at small children” the world perceived an inconsistency in a nation that preached freedom for all, though denied the very same right to its children. Ernest Green and the other eight students “learned unmistakably that they possessed irresistible power” during the crisis but only if they realised it and united against discrimination and racism.
The court case of Marbury v. Madison (1803) is credited and widely believed to be the creator of the “unprecedented” concept of Judicial Review. John Marshall, the Supreme Court Justice at the time, is lionized as a pioneer of Constitutional justice, but, in the past, was never really recognized as so. What needs to be clarified is that nothing in history is truly unprecedented, and Marbury v. Madison’s modern glorification is merely a product of years of disagreements on the validity of judicial review, fueled by court cases like Eakin v. Raub; John Marshall was also never really recognized in the past as the creator of judicial review, as shown in the case of Dred Scott v. Sanford.
The Hollow Hope examines the following research question: when can judicial processes be used to produce social change? (Rosenberg 1). Rosenberg starts out the book by describing the two different theories of the courts. The first theory, the Dynamic Court view, views the court as being powerful, vigorous, and potent proponents of change (Rosenberg 1). The second theory, the Constrained Court view, views the court in the complete opposite way. With this view the court is seen as weak, ineffective, and powerless (Rosenberg 3). In this view there are three different constraints that restrict the courts from producing effective political and social change. These constraints include: limited nature of constitutional rights, lack of judicial independence, and the lack of tools the courts need (Rosenberg 35). Even though there are constraints on the court there are conditions where the court is able to overcome the constraints.
Based on the pronouncements of the court on May 17, 1954, everyone in the courtroom was shocked after it became clear that Marshall was right in his claim about the unconstitutionality of legal segregation in American public schools. Essentially, this court’s decision became a most important turning point in U.S. history because the desegregation case had been won by an African American attorney. Additionally, this became a landmark decision in the sense that it played a big role in the crumbling of the discriminatory laws against African Americans and people of color in major socioeconomic areas, such as employment, education, and housing (Stinson, 2008). Ultimately, Marshall’s legal achievements contributed significantly to the criminal justice field.
Hariman, R. “Performing the Laws: Popular Trials and Social Knowledge” from Popular Trials: Rhetoric, Mass Media, and the Law, Robert Hariman, ed(s)., University of Alabama Press, 1990. 17-30.
"Histories, like ancient ruins, are the fictions of empires. While everything forgotten hands in dark dreams of the past, ever threatening to return...”, a quote from the movie Velvet Goldmine, expresses the thoughts that many supporters of integration may have felt because no one truly knew the effects that one major verdict could create. The Brown v. Board of Education decision was a very important watershed during the Civil Rights Movement. However, like most progressive decisions, it did not create an effective solution because no time limit was ever given. James Baldwin realized that this major oversight would lead to a “broken promise.”
Justice is often misconceived as injustice, and thus some essential matters that require more legal attentions than the others are neglected; ergo, some individuals aim to change that. The principles of civil disobedience, which are advocated in both “Civil Disobedience” by Henry David Thoreau and “Letter from Birmingham Jail” by Martin Luther King Jr. to the society, is present up to this time in the U.S. for that purpose.
The Supreme Court is perhaps most well known for the Brown vs. Board of Education decision in 1954. By declaring that segregation in schools was unconstitutional, Kevern Verney says a ‘direct reversal of the Plessy … ruling’1 58 years earlier was affected. It was Plessy which gave southern states the authority to continue persecuting African-Americans for the next sixty years. The first positive aspect of Brown was was the actual integration of white and black students in schools. Unfortunately, this was not carried out to a suitable degree, with many local authorities feeling no obligation to change the status quo. The Supreme Court did issue a second ruling, the so called Brown 2, in 1955. This forwarded the idea that integration should proceed 'with all deliberate speed', but James T. Patterson tells us even by 1964 ‘only an estimated 1.2% of black children ... attended public schools with white children’2. This demonstrates that, although the Supreme Court was working for Civil Rights, it was still unable to force change. Rathbone agrees, saying the Supreme Court ‘did not do enough to ensure compliance’3. However, Patterson goes on to say that ‘the case did have some impact’4. He explains how the ruling, although often ignored, acted ‘relatively quickly in most of the boarder s...
Dahl conducted his study on the decision making of the Supreme Court and whether the Court exercised its power of judicial review to counter majority will and protect minority rights or if it used the power to ratify the further preferences of the dominant “national law making majority.” From the results of Dahl’s study he builds numerous arguments throughout his article, “Decision-Making in a Democracy: the Supreme Court as a National Policy-Maker”. In what follows, I will thoroughly point out and explain each of the arguments that Dahl constructs in his article.
The mutation and progression of civil rights and the idea of what it means to be “American” can be examined in the differences between Dredd Scott, and Plessy v Ferguson compared with Brown v. Board of Education. This case was heard and decided ...
Throughout history, society has pushed the envelope with civil liberties and civil rights by tackling Supreme Court decisions. From the decision to incorporate the Bill of Rights- i.e the Bill of Liberties- to the need to eradicate the disparity of African Americans and women, America’s citizens have fought for equality since the birth of the United States.
Words can bring positive change to a community, be it a small town or the entire world - all it takes is two key components, delivery and content. This was certainly the case with Clarence Darrow’s 1926 concluding speech in defence of African American, Henry Sweet, accused of the murder of a white man. Darrow’s monumental eight-hour speech set a legal precedent when Sweet was acquitted of his murder charge. The speech, “Changed the status of Negros before the law and meant in respect to defending ones home and self in self defence, what applied to whites now, in practice and not just in word, apply to African Americans as well.” Clarence Darrow’s speech, along with Henry Sweet’s acquittal, is now considered huge milestone in the civil rights movement.
According to Martin Luther King Jr., “There are two types of laws: there are just and there are unjust laws” (King 293). During his time as civil rights leader, he advocated civil disobedience to fight the unjust laws against African-Americans in America. For instance, there was no punishment for the beatings imposed upon African-Americans or for the burning of their houses despite their blatant violent, criminal, and immoral demeanor. Yet, an African-American could be sentenced to jail for a passive disagreement with a white person such as not wanting to give up their seat to a white passenger on a public bus. Although these unjust laws have been righted, Americans still face other unjust laws in the twenty-first century.
I was told that my desire to enter the field of public interest would wane after my first year of community service. On the contrary, the realization of the power which a lawyer possesses has reinforced my desire to enter this arena. An advocate's work can have far reaching consequences. This is clearly true in public interest law, where the purpose is not simply to correct a wrong done in the past between two parties, but to alter the disparate treatment of an often under-represented class.
Robert N. Clinton, ‘Judges Must Make Law: A Realistic Appraisal of the Judicial Function in a Democratic Society’ [1981-1982] 67 Iowa L. Rev. 711 http://heinonline.org/HOL/Page?handle=hein.journals/ilr67&div=38&g_sent=1&collection=journals accessed 12 February 2012