The Samaritan’s dilemma occurs when giving charitable donations removes the incentive for the receiver to improve their own situation. When aid is given, the receiver initially has two options: they can use the aid to improve their situation, or they can trust that they will receive aid again and do nothing productive with the aid they receive. Good Samaritans evidently give charitable donations in hopes of the former, however we will see that this scenario does not necessarily play out in their favour (Coate 1995). The Samaritan’s dilemma often presents itself in the area of foreign aid, and there are certain measures the government can take to eliminate the uncertainty it causes. In this essay I will first discuss the significance of the …show more content…
Samaritan’s dilemma in general terms, then I will apply the observations to foreign aid and finally I will describe what the government can do to prevent it from occurring. Consider a situation where we have Country A, the giver of a charitable donation, and Country B, the receiver of the donation. Imagine that Country B has become the victim of a terrible natural disaster, and in light of this tragedy, Country A has found it within itself to donate funds to go towards first-aid initiatives and rebuilding projects. Country A trusts that Country B will use the financial aid to return to its original state before disaster struck. However, it cannot be known at the time of giving whether Country B will use this aid responsibly or not. This uncertainty that the giver faces is the first lynchpin of the Samaritan’s dilemma. The foreign aid situation above is not unlike the situation in which a well-off person considers giving a small donation to a homeless person. They will often wonder whether the homeless person will use the money to get himself out of poverty or to buy drugs, and there is no way of knowing the outcome at this point. As a result, many well-off individuals choose not to donate as they anticipate the worst, and consequently those homeless people who would have used the donation responsibly suffer. The same logic could also occur in our foreign aid example. The recipient country might have used the funds responsibly to rebuild their country, but the giving country has decided against giving a donation for fear that the funds would not have been put toward the rebuilding effort. The above description is only a brief introduction, so it is necessary to delve a bit deeper into the implications of the Samaritan’s dilemma before we proceed. Another lynchpin of the Samaritan’s dilemma is that the receiver of a donation faces some risk of loss if they do not receive another donation when they need it, such as unanticipated medical expenses or crop failure. In the case of a poor person, the responsible thing to do would be for them to buy some sort of insurance so that when disaster strikes they are not left to resolve the damages on their own. However, we see that many poor people continuously anticipate additional donations and therefore fail to see the value in purchasing insurance when the funds will be readily available through charity in any case. Coate (1995) states that the availability of charity for the poor has been suggested as a key factor in explaining the large fraction of low-income individuals without health insurance in the US. In addition, the reluctance of individuals to purchase insurance against natural disasters has been linked to the traditional generosity of the American public toward victims of natural disasters (Coate 1995). As a consequence of the poor failing to get insured, there are adverse efficiency effects. In the case of charity, the rich, not the poor, choose how much protection to give the poor against loss. There is no reason to expect the rich to choose the level of protection that is optimal for the poor person, which is one such source of inefficiency. Coate suggests that the government should ensure that the poor obtain insurance to restore efficiency. What Coate calls the “optimal transfer policy” would involve providing “in-kind” transfers of insurance (1995). If we apply these observations to the context of foreign aid, the activities of altruistic aid organizations and charitable governments are often counter-productive because they can increase poverty and worsen income distribution. Pedersen (2001) observes that recipient governments will adjust their circumstances in order to fraudulently qualify for aid because they know that the more poverty a donor observes, the more aid it will give, which is another source of inefficiency. Governments have a few options for alleviating the uncertainty caused by the Samaritan’s dilemma.
First we return to Coate’s optimal transfer policy involving in-kind transfers of insurance. By definition, in-kind transfers from the government are goods and services given to the poor instead of money. This system removes the possibility that the poor will abuse the charity by using it irresponsibly. Thus, this is a very effective method of eliminating the uncertainty burden on the giver. If a charitable government gives a suffering country a donation in the form of a good or service instead of a monetary transfer, the country will be forced to use the charity for its intended purpose. Another solution proposed by Coate is for the government to simply require that the country take insurance measures if it wants to receive continuing donations in the future. Presumably the recipient country would present some sort of proof of insurance and the charitable government would continue to provide donations. Coate takes this method a step further and states that the charitable government can also subsidize insurance by offering monetary transfers conditional on the country taking insurance, such as natural disaster insurance. However, the in-kind transfers remain the failsafe measure since with insurance requisite for donation policy or subsidized insurance policy the country could take the insurance but that would not necessarily stop it from using the rest of the charitable money for other less productive projects (Coate 1995). The fundamental problem with the first two measures is that there is no approach the charitable government can take to punish the recipient government without hurting the poor in the recipient country. Even if there is a contract between the giver and the receiver stating that the quality of life of the poor must increase by a certain amount in a set time, there is nothing the giver can do if the contract is broken. If the giver ceases donations,
the poor in the recipient country will continue to suffer (Pedersen 2001). We have seen that the Samaritan’s dilemma can be applied to foreign aid and that governments have one effective option for ameliorating the disadvantages it causes. Givers of aid remain uncertain as to how their donations will be used, and receivers have a certain risk of loss by forgoing responsible use of funds. The governments of charitable countries have several options for preventing recipient countries from using the donations irresponsibly, and providing in-kind donations are one of the most effective ways of accomplishing this goal. The problem of the Samaritan’s dilemma is a very fascinating concept to investigate and the applications of it are quite vast. However, the amount of detail necessary to fully understand its implications in this context exceeds the constraints of this essay, and the issue is admittedly very complex and calls for further research.
In this paper I will examine both Peter Singer’s and Onora O 'Neill 's positions on famine relief. I will argue that O’Neill’s position is more suitable than Singer’s extreme standpoint. First I will, present O’Neill’s argument. I will then present a possible counter-argument to one of my premises. Finally I will show how this counter-argument is fallacious and how O’Neill’s argument in fact goes through.
For this book report on The Samaritans Dilemma by Deborah Stone will consist of two chapters I am going to talk about chapters 2,4. I will talk about what Stone was trying to say in the chapters and either if I will agree or disagree with what she has to say or if I can actually be in the middle of the argument and be for it as well as against it. I will as well be providing information from the book The American Welfare State by Brian Glenn to show why I favor a side in the dilemma Stone is talking about. Seven Bad Arguments Against Help In chapter two Stone tries to cover objections that people have against the welfare state. In the first argument she goes on and talks about that by helping people it makes them more dependent on other people
This paper explores Peter Singer’s argument, in Famine, Affluence, and Morality, that we have morally required obligations to those in need. The explanation of his argument and conclusion, if accepted, would dictate changes to our lifestyle as well as our conceptions of duty and charity, and would be particularly demanding of the affluent. In response to the central case presented by Singer, John Kekes offers his version, which he labels the and points out some objections. Revisions of the principle provide some response to the objections, but raise additional problems. Yet, in the end, the revisions provide support for Singer’s basic argument that, in some way, we ought to help those in need.
How much money is one morally obligated to give to relief overseas? Many In people would say that although it is a good thing to do, one is not obligated to give anything. Other people would say that if a person has more than he needs, then he should donate a portion of what he has. Peter Singer, however, proposes a radically different view. His essay, “Famine, Affluence, and Morality,” focuses on the Bengal crisis in 1971 and claims that one is morally obligated to give as much as possible. His thesis supports the idea that “We ought to give until we reach the level of marginal utility – that is, the level at which, by giving more, I would cause as much suffering to myself or my dependents as I would relieve by my gift” (399). He says that one's obligation to give to people in need half-way around the world is just as strong as the obligation to give to one's neighbor in need. Even more than that, he says that one should keep giving until, by giving more, you would be in a worse position than the people one means to help. Singer's claim is so different than people's typical idea of morality that is it is easy to quickly dismiss it as being absurd. Saying that one should provide monetary relief to the point that you are in as bad a position as those receiving your aid seems to go against common sense. However, when the evidence he presents is considered, it is impossible not to wonder if he might be right.
... aid across the world. As we have established that we do have an obligation to redistribute globally in a cosmopolitan perspective, distributing wealth however we may need to rethink what the best assistance is. Amaryta Sen conveys that before sending aid to the third world state, we would need to fully understand the limitation of freedom in the country. Redistributing wealth to global countries requires it to be evaluated by the economic shortage that they are suffering and to see whether it will be efficient in the long run. The more effective ways to contribute would be to international relief agencies or NGO’s that would pursue international development projects to help those in poverty or the alternative option by Tom Campbell’s idea of a ‘Global humanitarian levy’ which suggests a more appropriate taxation on all citizens to collectively aid those in need.
Hares takes on a Kantian Approach; a duty. He uses a concept that a fetus is not a “person” because it does not have the rights. He says that the characteristic and a duty to have a right are considered as “human beings”. Hare says that we don’t know whether the fetus would turn into a human adult or a horse (Luper and Brown, p. 585). He presents two principles: Pro-life and Pro-choice; life and liberty. If mothers terminate a pregnancy, then she is offending the principle of preserving life, and if a third-party stops the mother from an abortion, then they are defending against the mother’s pro-life and pro-choice decisions (Luper and Brown, p. 586). . The fetus should be considered as an “it” rather than a “person” However, Hares says that
Most people feel that they should help the needy in some way or another. The problem is how to help them. This problem generally arises when there is a person sitting on the side of the road in battered clothes with a cardboard sign asking for some form of help, almost always in the form of money. Yet something makes the giver uneasy. What will they do with this money? Do they need this money? Will it really help them? The truth of the matter is, it won't. However, there are things that can be done to help the needy. Giving money to a reliable foundation will help the helpless, something that transferring money from a pocket to a man's tin can will never do.
In this paper, I will argue against two articles which were written against Singer’s view, and against helping the poor countries in general. I will argue against John Arthur’s article Famine Relief and the Ideal Moral Code (1974 ) ,and Garrett Hardin’s article Lifeboat Ethics: the Case Against Helping the Poor ( 1976); I will show that both articles are exaggerating the negative consequences of aiding the poor, as well as building them on false assumptions. Both Arthur and Hardin are promoting the self-interest without considering the rights of others, and without considering that giving for famine relief means giving life to many children.
The United States is one of the leading suppliers of Foreign Aid in the world, and even though the US gives billions, European countries give aid money to the same countries, this causes many areas of the Middle East, Africa, and Asia to be almost fully dependent on foreign aid. This means that without aid from other countries, they would not be able to support themselves at all. Foreign aid is meant to help countries that are struggling with civil unrest, disease, or natural disasters, it is not meant to help keep the country out of debt, but that is where more and more of the US and The EU’s foreign aid budget is going. The question is, does all this money actually go where it is intended? It should be going towards the government and to help the people, but in many cases, the countries government does not have the resources to properly track the flow of money. The countries in most cases have poor infrastructure and corrupt or oppressive leaders, not always at a national level, but in the towns and cities. So this means there is almost no way to oversee the flow of foreign aid through the country, all we can see is that their situations aren't getting any better and the countries are still impoverished. If this is the case, where are the millions of dollars going? Countries like Afghanistan and Iraq receive the most money from American foreign aid and European aid, yet they are still under oppressive governmental rule and there is still an extreme difference between the rich and poor. Garrett Harding’s theory of “Lifeboat Ethics” exemplifies how not giving aid to others will allow the strongest of society to thrive, while teaching the impoverished to help themselves. He believes that giving aid to poor countries will only make ...
According to Ronald F. White, there are three moral theories that attempt to clear the gray area between good and bad behavior, and truth varies among individuals based on their beliefs (279). Hardin argues based on the teleological ethical theory, claiming that an action is immoral if the negative consequences outweigh the positive consequences (White 280). According to Hardin, rich nations should not assist poor nations because the financial disaster that it will impose upon the wealthy will outweigh the justice and help given to the poor (291). However, there is another moral theory that serves as a counterargument to Hardin’s approach. Deontological theorists could argue that aiding the poor is a moral law that should never be broken, no matter the consequences (White 281). Because Hardin’s argument is based solely on his beliefs and one moral theory, it loses practical validity as it can be argued against from many
First off, wow, just wow. I'm very unsure of how to react to this situation. The Samaritan law states if you see someone in trouble, you help. A person can be liable if they ignore someone in danger, understandable. This, however, opens a can of worms I can't wrap my brain around. On one hand, Van Horn did crash into a light pole and then caused permanent spinal to this woman, but she was just trying to help. Van Horn is not a medical professional and was just responding the best way they could have. I feel sympathy for Ms.Torti and what happened to her, but I wish this case was not continuing. This is a tragedy and it just sad on both sides.
Emergency situations can call for an erratic response to someone’s life in which a person is injured or one’s life is in danger. The decision to be a hero or to be saved must be made. Despite the scenario, high emotion may be involved for both the hero and the one being saved. The hero could make the scene worse or cause more injury to the one being save. Furthermore, the hero could be sued for negligence. Issues of being sued could play an impact when a person makes the decision whether to be the hero or remain a bystander. Consequently, the “Good Samaritan Law” benefit those who could be potentially be accused of negligence after giving emergency care. However, lay responders must comply to legal regulations
Peter Singer said; “If it is in our power to prevent something bad from happening, without thereby sacrificing anything of comparable moral importance, we ought, morally, to do it” (Famine, Affluence, and Morality). As human beings, we have a moral compulsion to help other people, despite the verity that they may be strangers, especially when whatever type of aid we may render can in no approach have a more significant consequence on our own life.
“No one would remember the Good Samaritan if he’d only had good intentions – he had money too.”
In the Parable of the Good Samaritan a lawyers asks Jesus a question “Who is my neighbor”? Jesus then tells him who do pray upon and what does the law say and then the lawyer responds and says that you should love God with all of your heart and soul and with all of your strength and mind. Jesus tells him that is right and you answered the question correctly. Jesus explains to the lawyer that a man was going across Jerusalem to Jericho and the man got beat down by burglars and they left him alone completely exhausted and almost dead. A cleric came through the road and when he saw the man who got beat down he moved across the opposite side. When the Levite came and saw the man he also moved across the opposite side. Then lastly a Samaritan came to the