Wait a second!
More handpicked essays just for you.
More handpicked essays just for you.
Short debate on animal rights
Animal rights evaluated
Written discussion about animal rights
Don’t take our word for it - see why 10 million students trust us with their essay needs.
The Case for Animal Right
Recently, some philosophers began to take action on fighting for animal rights. One of them, philosopher Tom Regan, is well-known for his animal rights theories. In his book The Case for Animal Rights, Regan argues that animals should have their rights, and we should not allow speciesism to happen anymore. By using the term inherent value, which is referring to experiencing subject of a life, Regan starts his argument by saying that all of us, despite being human or non-human animals, have equal inherent value, which provides the basis for rights claims, yet inherent value and rights require equal respect. Thus, animals are deserving of equal respect. With this conclusion, he makes a movement to fight for the total
His first premise is that all of us, human and non-human animals, have equal inherent value. According to Regan, all human beings, regardless of sex, race, religion, birthplace, etc., altogether have inherent value, possess it equally, and have an equal right to be treated with respect. He states that we should not limit this inherent value only to human, but to non-human animals as well even though animals lack many abilities that humans possess; for examples, they are not able to read, to use technology, to write a philosophy paper. In this case, the fact is that some humans, such as feral children and people with mental disabilities, are also incapable of performing these acts, yet we should never say that they have less inherent values than the others. That is, we should apply the similar condition to animals, which implies that humans and animals, both of who experience the subject of life, have inherent value. As a consequence, this indication leads to the next part of his argument for animal
Nevertheless, his argument has some weak points. In this section, I will present my strongest objection to his argument, that humans and animals need to follow the social contract altogether in order to have rights claims, in response to the second premise that equal inherent value provides the basis for rights claims. In fact, a right claim requires responsibilities, duties, and obligations of the parties that take part in the event of the rights claim. As a result, if we apply the same basis for rights claims to animals, they should also hold responsibilities for these right claims, which is impossible in this case. Let’s see an example, if we don’t “touch” animal at all, I wonder whether all of them will act the same with us or not. The answer is obvious, that we still have to avoid the carnivores. Therefore, my points show that this premise is weak, which leads to the invalidation of the conclusion that animals are deserving of equal
Regan, Tom. “The Case for Animal Rights.” In Animal Rights and Human Obligations, 2 ed.. New Jersey: Prentice Hall, 1989.
Peter Singer’s arguments in Animal Liberation have often been misunderstood. The most mutual, and important, misunderstanding among professional thinkers consists in the belief that the moral argument advanced by Animal Liberation is created on utilitarianism, besides not, as is in fact the situation, on the belief of no maleficence. Peter Singer’s Animal Liberation is surely one of the most persuasive, powerful and efficient works of applied integrities ever printed. Since the publication of the first edition in April 5, 1973, Singer’s work has been spoken, and its main theses enthusiastically argued by others. In the essay Singer’s tone was very rational and patient,
The essay “Ill-gotten Gains” first appeared in a book called ‘Health Care Ethics’ and was written by Tom Regan, a renowned philosopher, author and animal rights advocate. The essay appeared again in Tom Regan’s best known book called ‘The Case for Animal Rights’ which states Regan’s beliefs regarding animal rights and provides a sound argument as to why animals should not be exploited for our own gain. Tom Regan believes all animal use that benefits humans is morally unacceptable, including for food, entertainment, labour, experiments and research. “Ill-gotten Gains” argues that to be on the right moral path we need to view all individuals with inherent value as a ‘subject of a life’. Regan argues that any practice in which a ‘subject of life’ is used as a resource is immoral, not because of emotion, but because of reason.
...nger states “Equality is a moral idea, not an assertion of fact. There is no logically compelling reason for assuming that a factual difference in ability between two people justifies any difference in the amount of consideration we give to their needs and interests”. Singer argues that, as there is no justification for unequal treatment of human beings based on capacity, it is also unjustifiable to treat human and non-human animals differently based on their capacities.
Regan, Tom. “The Case for Animal Rights.” In Defense of Animals. Ed. Peter Singer. New York:
Lastly, he argues that sentience is the only characteristic that should be considered in terms of granting animal rights. This leads him to the conclusion that “if a being suffers, there can be no moral justification for refusing to take that suffering into consideration. The principle of equality requires that its suffering be counted equally with the like suffering – insofar as rough comparisons can be made – of any other being”. Before I continue, it is important to note the distinction that Singer makes between “equal considerations” and “equal treatment”. For Singer, “equal consideration for different beings may lead to different treatment and different rights”....
In his essay ‘Three Wrong Leads in a Search for an Environmental Ethic: Tom Regan on Animal Rights, Inherent Values, and Deep Ecology’, Partridge claims that Singer and Regan both miss a significant element to the nature of rights: they only have a moral basis, not a biological basis. For Partridge, how alike human beings and other animals are in terms of biology is irrelevant. What matters instead is that other animals show no capacities of rationality or self-conscious, which is what makes us moral. For Partridge, this consequently excludes other animals from being rights
As an advocate of animal rights, Tom Regan presents us with the idea that animals deserve to be treated with equal respect to humans. Commonly, we view our household pets and select exotic animals in different regard as oppose to the animals we perceive as merely a food source which, is a notion that animal rights activists
I, therefore, feel that Peter Singer’s argument on “All Animals Are Equal” is true and that the equality of consideration can and should lead to equal treatment among those animals
In conclusion, I agree with Tom Regan’s perspective of the rights view, as it explores the concept of equality, and the concept of rightful treatment of animals and humans. If a being is capable of living, and experiencing life, then they are more than likely capable of feeling pleasure and pain, except in a few instances. If humans are still treated in a respectable and right way even if some cannot vote, or think for themselves, then it is only fair that animals who also lack in some of these abilities be treated as equals. As Regan puts it, “pain is pain, wherever it occurs” (1989).
Tom Regan, “The Case for Animal Rights,” in In Defense of Animals, ed. Peter Singer (Oxford:
A. A. “The Case Against Animal Rights.” Animal Rights Opposing Viewpoints. Ed. Janelle Rohr. San Diego: Greenhaven Press, 1989.
... concept. An animal cannot follow our rules of morality, “Perhaps most crucially, what other species can be held morally accontable” (Scully 44). As a race humans must be humane to those that cannot grasp the concept. Animals do not posess human rights but they posess the right to welfare and proper treatment by their handlers.
However, it is the purpose of this essay to convince the reader otherwise. The question at hand is: do animals deserve rights? It must certainly be true. Humans deserve rights and this claim is made on numerous appeals. Of one of the pertinent pleas is made on the claim that humans can feel emotions. More importantly, that humans are capable of suffering, and that to inflict such pain is unethical. Those who observe the tortures of the Nazi Concentration Camp are instilled with a humane creed held for all humans. But if there is no significant gulf between humans, that is to say there is no gulf based on skin color, creed, or gender that will make one human more or less valuable than any other, then by what right can a gulf be drawn out between humans and our fellow creatures? The suffering of humans is why we sympathize with each other. Since animals suffer, they deserve our sympathy.
Humans place themselves at the top of the sociological tier, close to what we as individuals call our pets who have a sentimental value in our lives. Resource animal’s on the other hand have a contributory value within our lives: they provide us with meat and other important resources. In order to determine the boundaries between how we treat animals as pets and others simply as resources, utilitarians see these “resource animals” as tools. They contemplate the welfare significances of animals as well as the probable welfares for human-beings. Whereas deontologists see actions taken towards these “resources animals” as obligations regardless of whom or what they harm in the process. The objection to these theories are, whose welfare are we