This paper aims to explore Judith Jarvis Thomson’s arguments mostly for abortion in her article “Judith Jarvis Thomson: A Defense of Abortion”, from Philosophy & Public Affairs
Volume 1. She declares that abortion should be a provided choice because the mother has a right to her own body. She also believes that abortion should be morally permissible due to instances in which the future mother is placed under force and is unable to control the production of a child. Lastly, she further defends her position by asserting that a woman may be at risk of having a child when having sex due to defective contraceptives. After analyzing Thomson’s argument, this document will examine the ways in which her argument is specious and how she follows feminist
…show more content…
ethics. The paper will also explore another author who has argued against Thomson’s arguments: Don Marquis. Judith Jarvis Thomson believes that the act of abortion is morally right for a variety of reasons. Her first defense is that the mother has a right to her own body. She argues that there are instances in which the future mother is placed under force and is unable to control the production of a child. Lastly, she writes that the woman may have been placed under a risk in which she is in a situation in which the child has been conceived due to faulty contraceptives. In her first argument, she argues that the mother has the right to her reproductive freedom. To start her essay, she begins with a standard argument against abortion; “every person has a right to life. So the fetus has a right to life” (Thomson). However, she also brings to light that a mother has the right to her own body, so, the question is what is the stronger right, the mother’s right to her body, or, the child’s right to live? Thomson then goes to respond that those who do not defend abortion would reason that the fetus’ right to live is stronger. However, that is not always a definite statement, especially with both the mother and child being innocent. This ultimately claims that the abortion may not be performed under the assumption that the right to life is not always absolute. In Judith Jarvis Thomson’s second argument, she reasons that there are instances in which the future mother is placed under force and is unable to control the production of a child. One main example of these types of situations is called rape or a strained sexual assault. She creates an analogy to this form of abuse. In this, a person is kidnapped and awoken only to discover that they have been attached to a famous Violinist’s kidneys for nine months because the person is the only person whom can allow the violinist his, or her, life (Thomson). In this comparison, the mother is the person being kidnapped, and the violinist is the fetus. She is entitling the reader to make the assumption that the person being kidnapped should have the right to be unplugged because he, or she, has been kidnapped and taken from their own free will. Thomson even declares the following: “I imagine you would regard this as outrageous, which suggests that something really is wrong with that plausible-sounding argument I mentioned a moment ago” (Thomson). She continues to debate by stating that the mother did not “volunteer” to have a child and that the mother would have to spend “nine months of her pregnancy in bed” (Thomson). She then taunts opposers by stating that some would still be against abortion if the mother would be forced to spend her pregnancy in bed for “nine years” or the “rest of the mother’s life” (Thomson). Thomson also argues the woman may have been placed under a risk in which she is in a situation in which the child has been conceived due to faulty contraceptives as a way to prove that abortion is an acceptable procedure. Thomson supports her case by creating an analogy between someone opening their window and a burglar sneaking in: “If the room is stuffy, and I therefore open a window to air it, and a burglar climbs in, it would be absurd to say, "Ah, now he can stay, she's given him a right to the use of her house--for she is partially responsible for his presence there, having voluntarily done what enabled him to get in, in full knowledge that there are such things as burglars” (Thomson). She is comparing the fetus to the burglar and the mother to the person who opens their window. She then further supports her argument by recreating the scenario, but, this time, there are bars on the windows, which have a defect. This is her case for saying that faulty contraceptives can still lead to unjust, unwanted pregnancies. Thomson's perspective on abortion is that the procedure is morally correct, based upon the reasoning provided. Thomson’s view towards the subject of abortion follows the layout of the feminist moral theory. This is given as she believes that the mother should have the right to control her own body, which follows the second wave of feminist ethics. The feminist moral theory follows the premise of gender equality and is said to have three to four major waves. The second wave lasted from around the 1960’s to the 1980’s, according to Caroline Dorey-Stein, from the website, progressive women’s leadership (Dorey-Stein). During this section in time, feminism was “focused on the workplace, sexuality, family and reproductive rights” (Dorey-Stein), which included the rejection of monogamy and a greater increase in support for abortion. Thomson seems to imply that she subscribes to feminist ethics due to the fact that she believes that abortion leads to the happiness of the mother in guaranteeing a portion of her reproductive rights. Judith Jarvis Thomson’s views on abortion are wrong for numerous reasons.
One criticism is shown through the utilitarian perspective on the thought experiment of the famous violinist. Thomson wants the reader to believe that being hooked to the machine is morally unjust. She says her concerns by acknowledging that the situation is “outrageous” and that there is something “wrong with that plausible-sounding argument” (Thomson). However, to a utilitarian, it would make more sense to stay connected to the violinist because it would allow him/her to live and make all the members of the “Society of Music Lovers” full of content. However, if one were to unplug themselves, it would only be pleasurable for themselves. This would still be true under the circumstance that one was kidnapped and if one were to be kept in a hospital bed for nine months. Another criticism of Thomson’s view is that if she believes that no one has the moral obligation to treat others in a special manner, essentially being ‘unselfish’, then people can treat anyone as strangers. She reasons that no one has the moral obligation to treat nicely by using her two boys and chocolate comparison: There are two brothers. A box of chocolates is given to the older boy. He eats the box all by himself while “his small brother watching enviously” (Thomson). She then makes the argument that the boy is not being unjust because he does not have a moral obligation to share. However, the statement on morality may seem crude. …show more content…
For example, the declaration would imply that no one should do anything as simple has opening the door for a pregnant woman, or helping someone pick up fallen objects. To go further, this is also suggesting that one should not care for their family, or anyone who has cared for them, in a dire situation, because one does not have the moral obligation to. For example, if one’s mother or anyone that has cared for them, has a fatal kidney disease, one would donate their organ. However, according to Thomson, one would not be morally obliged to because she took care of them out of the kindness of her heart, not for anything in return. The kidney belongs to them and can keep it. Thomson’s view on abortion could also be criticized because, according to the author of “Response to Judith Jarvis Thomson’s A Defense for Abortion”, Thomson ignores family law. Since Thomson creates the assumption that the fetus is a human, then the parents have a “responsibility for their unborn children”. An article College Term Papers asserts that according to legal scholars Dennis J. Horan and Burke J. Balche, "All 50 states, the District of Columbia, American Samoa, Guam, and the U.S. Virgin Islands have child abuse and neglect statutes which provide for the protection of a child who does not receive needed medical care." They further claim that "a review of cases makes it clear that these statutes are properly applied to secure emergency medical treatment and sustenance (food or water, whether given orally or through intravenous or nasogastic tube) for children when parents, with or without the acquiescence of physicians, refuse to provide it" (College Term Papers). This would mean that once a fetus is aborted, then the laws were broken, so, abortion would not be (Marquis) legally acceptable. Due to these reasons, Judith Jarvis Thomson’s views on abortion is necessarily unreasonable. Other critics reject Judith Jarvis Thomson’s reasoning on abortion that comes about in her article. Don Marquis was, according to John Batteiger, “a celebrated New York newspaper columnist and humorist in the early decades of the last century” (Batteiger). In his article, Why Abortion is Immoral, he suggests that Judith Jarvis Thomson is mistaken because of her stance on the scenario that sometimes a woman’s right to her body overthrows the fetus’ right to live. On one hand, Thomson makes the argument that the right to live is not an absolute right; she reasons this by creating her violinist analogy. On the other hand, Marquis advocates that killing is one of the highest offenses. He believes that abortion is essentially identical to murder as he declares the following: What primarily makes killing wrong is neither its effect on the murderer nor its effect on the victim’s friends and relatives, but its effect on the victim.
The loss of one’s life is one of the greatest losses one can suffer. The loss of one’s life deprives one of all the experiences, activities, projects, and enjoyments which would otherwise have constituted one’s future (Marquis 4).
He judges that the fetus would be considered the victim and by completing an abortion, one would be depriving it of its possibilities. He believes that right to life is the most important right one can have and to take it away would be one of the most immoral acts one can perform. So given Don Marquis’ argument, Judith Jarvis Thomson’s argument seems to be feeble because of her reasoning, which promotes that the right to live is not absolute, is
incorrect. In conclusion, Judith Jarvis Thomson argues in favor of the use of abortion as a medical procedure. This is for a variety of reasons including that the mother has a right to her own body. To follow, should the mother be placed in a position of force and is unable to control the production of a child, abortion should be moral. Finally, she fights for her case by stating that the woman may have been at risk to having a child when having sex due to defective contraceptives. The Merriam-Webster dictionary defines abortion as “a medical procedure used to end a pregnancy and cause the death of the fetus” (Merriam-Webster). This paper disagrees with Judith Jarvis Thomson’s findings largely because of her use of her misleading violinist analogy. To follow, Thomson’s principle that no one has the obligation to treat other nicely is immoral because it would mean that one does not have to care for people who have cared for them. Lastly, she fails to follow family law when making her statements.
Don Marquis primary argument lays on the fact that a fetus possesses a property, the possession of which in an adult human being is sufficient to make killing an adult human being wrong, makes abortion wrong (Gedge & Waluchow, 2012, p224). This property is the right to a valuable future. Marquis argument defends the position that abortion is morally wrong against pro-choice arguments, including the irrationality of a fetus, the lack of a fetus desire to live, and the fetus not being considered a victim.
Judith Jarvis Thomson, in "A Defense of Abortion", argues that even if we grant that fetuses have a fundamental right to life, in many cases the rights of the mother override the rights of a fetus. For the sake of argument, Thomson grants the initial contention that the fetus has a right to life at the moment of conception. However, Thomson explains, it is not self-evident that the fetus's right to life will always outweigh the mother's right to determine what goes on in her body. Thomson also contends that just because a woman voluntarily had intercourse, it does not follow that the fetus acquires special rights against the mother. Therefore, abortion is permissible even if the mother knows the risks of having sex. She makes her points with the following illustration. Imagine that you wake up one morning and find that you have been kidnapped, taken to a hospital, and a famous violist has been attached to your circulatory system. You are told that the violinist was ill and you were selected to be the host, in which the violinist will recover in nine months, but will die if disconnected from you before then. Clearly, Thomson argues, you are not morally required to continue being the host. In her essay she answers the question: what is the standard one has to have in order to be granted a right to life? She reflects on two prospects whether the right to life is being given the bare minimum to sustain life or ir the right to life is merely the right not to be killed. Thomson states that if the violinist has more of a right to life then you do, then someone should make you stay hooked up to the violinist with no exceptions. If not, then you should be free to go at a...
Thomson starts off her paper by explaining the general premises that a fetus is a person at conception and all persons have the right to life. One of the main premises that Thomson focuses on is the idea that a fetus’ right to life is greater than the mother’s use of her body. Although she believes these premises are arguable, she allows the premises to further her explanation of why abortion could be
Marquis believes abortion to be extremely immoral. However he mentions that there are exceptions in rare but certain circumstances where abortion is acceptable. We can infer that these instances would include situations that would put the mother or child at serious risk by keeping the fetus. He is frustrated that this idea has received minimal support recently. As a result he wants to influence change in society in hopes of receiving the support and publicity this topic deserves. Marquis’ primary argument stems from the idea of killing in general. He explains it is immoral to kill an adult because it prematurely deprives the human of something they may have valued at the time they were killed, as well as something they may had valued in the future. Although the victim may not realize it at the time of their death, they certainly had a valuable future ahead of them to experience which has been cut short. We are the only ones who can decide what is valuable to them; in this case we value some things more than others, and this concept differs from person to person. For example, in the present I value the life I am given and the opportunity I have to earn my degree at Villanova University while also valuing my future as well knowing that I have a chance to be successful in the future. Although I have not succeeded yet, I still value that opportunity I have and the life I’m capable of achieving through earning a degree. Therefore, he connects this same theory to the life of a fetus. By killing the fetus the result is the same, we are depriving it of its futur...
In Don Marquis’s essay “Why Abortion is Immoral” he argues that abortion is immoral because he believes that abortion is morally equivalent to killing an adult human being. Marquis’ argument takes the following form:
Thus, Marquis’ argument for his pro-life view on abortion is flawed because one of his premises is not completely correct. Marquis argues that fetuses, children, and adults are all human beings and have the right to life. Also, Marquis says that losing one’s life is one of the worst things that can happen to a human being. So he technically declares that it is horrible to die, but not the worst thing to happen to someone. He starts out with the first premise about how the killing of a fetus deprives it of its potential future experiences.
In Judith Jarvis Thompson’s article “A Defense of Abortion” she explores the different arguments against abortion presented by Pro –Life activists, and then attempts to refute these notions using different analogies or made up “for instances” to help argue her point that women do have the right to get an abortion. She explains why abortion is morally permissible using different circumstances of becoming pregnant, such as rape or unplanned pregnancy.
In her article Thomson starts off by giving antiabortionists the benefit of the doubt that fetuses are human persons. She adds that all persons have the right to life and that it is wrong to kill any person. Also she states that someone?s right to life is stronger than another person?s autonomy and that the only conflict with a fetuses right to life is a mother?s right to autonomy. Thus the premises make abortion impermissible. Then Thomson precedes to attacks the premise that one?s right to autonomy can be more important to another?s right to life in certain situations. She uses quite an imaginative story to display her point of view. Basically there is a hypothetical situation in which a very famous violinist is dying. Apparently the only way for the violinist to survive is to be ?plugged? into a particular woman, in which he could use her kidneys to continue living. The catch is that the Society of Music Lovers kidnapped this woman in the middle of the night in order to obtain the use of her kidneys. She then woke up and found herself connected to an unconscious violinist. This obviously very closely resembles an unwanted pregnancy. It is assumed that the woman unplugging herself is permissible even though it would kill the violinist. Leading to her point of person?s right to life is not always stronger than another person?s right to have control over their own body. She then reconstructs the initial argument to state that it is morally impermissible to abort a fetus if it has the right to life and has the right to the mother?s body. The fetus has the right to life but only has the right to a ...
Thomson’s argument is presented in three components. The first section deals with the now famous violinist thought experiment. This experiment presents a situation in which you wake up one morning and discover you have been kidnapped and hooked up to an ailing violinist so that his body would have the use of your kidneys for the next nine months. The intuitive and instinctive reaction to this situation is that you have no moral duty to remain hooked up to the violinist, and more, that he (or the people who kidnapped you) does not have the right to demand the use of your body for this period. From a deontological point of view, it can be seen that in a conflict between the right of life of the fetus and the right to bodily integrity of the mother, the mother’s rights will trump those of the fetus. Thomson distills this by saying “the right to life consists not in the right not to be killed, but rather in the right not to be killed unjustly”.
To conclude, Marquis’s argument that abortion is wrong is incorrect. Thomson gives many examples of why Marquis is wrong, including that the mother’s right to her body
Judith Thomson’s “A Defense of Abortion” is an essay where Thomson argues that abortion is not impermissible. To be even more precise, she argues for abortion should also be sometimes permissible, but she also grants that there are certain situations in which getting an abortion would be immoral. “Most opposition to abortion relies on the premise that the fetus is a human being, a person, from the moment of conception.” (Thomson, 48). She uses the rhetorical triangle to help her achieve her argument about abortion. Which uses ethos, pathos, and logos to influence her providing the argument surrounding abortion.
Why Abortion is Immoral by Don Marquis is an essay that claims that abortion is morally wrong, and uses one argument in particular to explain why. He argues that many of us would agree that it is wrong to kill a human, and if you believe that, then you should also have that view on abortions. If you think killing is wrong then you think all killing is wrong and the persons biological state, whether it is when a person is a fetus, one year old, or thirty years old, makes no difference. He then explains that killing is wrong not only because it is immoral, but wrong because it deprives the victim of life and the enjoyments one would have otherwise experienced; which Marquis believes is the greatest loss one can suffer (Marquis, 189). Given certain circumstances, Marquis agrees there are cases where killing is acceptable, but nonetheless it is immoral.
Thomson concludes that there are no cases where the person pregnant does not have the right to chose an abortion. Thomson considers the right to life of the pregnant person by presenting the case of a pregnant person dying as a result from their pregnancy. In this case, the right of the pregnant person to decide what happens to their body outweighs both the fetus and the pregnant person 's right to life. The right to life of the fetus is not the same as the pregnant person having to die, so as not to infringe on the right of the fetus. In the case of the violinist, their necessity for your body for life is not the same as their right over the use of your body. Thomson argues that having the right to life is not equal to having the right to use the body of another person. They argue that this is also the case, even if the the pregnant person knowingly participated in intercourse and knew of the possibility of pregnancy. In this case it would seem that abortion would not be permissible since the pregnancy was not by force. However, we are reverted back to the case of rape. If a fetus conceived voluntarily has the right not to be aborted due to how it was conceived, then the fetus conceived from rape should also have that same right. Instead of creating a distinction of cases where the fetus has a right to use the body of a pregnant person, Thomson instead makes a distinction of when abortion would be morally
She defends this statement with the violinist case. In the violinist case, a person is abducted by the Society of Music Lovers and attached to a famous violinist because he or she alone has the correct blood type to filter toxins from the violinist’s kidneys. The person must now stay hooked up to the violinist for nine months because if he or she were to unplug from the violinist, he would surely die. The violinist has a right to life and to unplug from him would be to kill him. Thomson believes that the person who was abducted and a woman who becomes pregnant as the result of a rape are both put in a situation in which another person relies on the woman’s body for benefit through no fault of her own. According to Thomson, being abducted is like being raped because in both situations the person affected is not giving consent to the actions. Like the violinist using the person’s body to detoxify his kidneys, a fetus relies on the mother for nutrition and shelter. The general principle Thomson takes from the case that she perceives to be analogous to having an abortion in the case of pregnancy by rape is that if an innocent person becomes involved in a situation in which another is dependent upon the innocent person’s body for benefit or even to maintain his or her life through no fault of the innocent person, then that person
According to Judith Thomson in her book “A Defense of Abortion”, a human embryo is a person who has a right to life. But, just because the human fetus has the right to life does not mean that the mother will be forced to carry it (Thomson, 48). Naturally, abortion may be seen as the deliberate termination of a pregnancy before the fetal viability. Though people have understood this, the topic of abortion has remained a controversial issue in the world. Individuals are divided into “Pro-choice” and “Pro-life” debaters depending on their opinion on the morality of the action. "Pro-life," the non-consequentialist side, is the belief that abortion is wrong, generally because it equates to killing. "Pro-choice," the consequentialist view, however,