Thomas Aquinas inherently affirmed in the teachings of the Catholic Church. Born in Italy in 1225 to a noble family, Thomas was one of at least nine children. He was a highly educated man, beginning his education at the Abbey of Monte Cassino, moving on to the University of Naples. Thomas had a strong belief in God and aspired to prove God’s actuality. During his life, Aquinas produced numerous works on the subject the most notable being the Summa contra Gentiles and the Summa Theologica . He leaves us a legacy as a great theologian and philosopher, often compared to Aristotle. “Much of Thomas’s personal studies went into ‘exposition’, as he usually called it, of works of Aristotle. Having embarked on what would become the Summa Theological, he clearly found Aristotle’s De Anima very helpful in his own theological accounts of the soul.” (Kerr 27)
His life spanned forty-nine years and produced over an astonishing sixty works within that time. “Aquinas wrote tirelessly during most of his life, producing works that the faithful call inspired: De Principiis Naturae (On the Principle of Nature), De Ente et Essentia (On Being and Essence), and his commentaries on Aristotle’s Physics, Metaphysics, De Anima, and Nicomachean Ethics. His Summa contra Gentiles is a work of apologetics, and his greatest work, Summa Theologica, presents reasoned argument in favor of faith; within Roman Catholicism it is considered a near sacred text.” (Porter 62)
The Summa Contra Gentiles states “Accordingly we must first show that every agent, by its action, intends an end. “ (Pegis 429) Aquinas reaffirms what Aristotle had stated about the beginning of Metaphysic. Aquinas claims, truth is the end or purpose of the universe because the end of ...
... middle of paper ...
...th, being raised in the Catholic church I do believe in St. Thomas’ teaching, I have been taught them all my life.
Works Cited:
Kennedy, Daniel. "St. Thomas Aquinas." The Catholic Encyclopedia. Vol. 14. New York: Robert Appleton Company, 1912. 24 Jul. 2011 12 .
Kerr, Fergus. Thomas Aquinas: a very short introduction. Oxford University Press, USA, 2009. 19, 27, 29 102. Print
Pegis, Anton C. Introduction to St. Thomas. New York, NY: Random House, 1948. 26-27, 429. Print.
Porter, Burton F. What the Tortoise Taught Us: The Story of Philosophy. Plymouth, UK: Rowman & Littlefield Pub Inc, 2010. 62-65. Print.
Strathern, Paul. Thomas Aquinas in 90 minutes. Chicago: Ivan R. Dee, 1998. 7. Print.
Wolff, Robert Paul. Ten Great Works of Philosophy. New York, NY: The Penguin Group, 1969. 97. Print.
Aquinas, St. Thomas. COMMENTARY on SAINT PAUL'S EPISTLE to the GALATIANS. Trans. F. R. Larcher. Albany: Magi Books, 1996.
existence to those who could not accept or believe God on faith alone. Aquinas’ first way
St. Thomas Aquinas presents five arguments to demonstrate the existence of God. However, this paper focuses on the fifth argument. The fifth argument is regarded as the Teleological Argument and states that things that lack intelligence act for some end or purpose. While the fifth argument satisfies God’s existence for Aquinas, some contemporary readers would argue that Aquinas neglects the laws of physics. Others argue that Aquinas allows a loophole in his argument so that the Catholic conception of God is not the only intelligent designer.
From Thomas’ youth to his untimely death, he was God’s tool. Thomas hoped to keep the Church of England pure from outside influences, and today we strive to keep ourselves pure from the taints of sin. Thomas’ sainthood is an example for each person alive today to cease the day, and be the best version of yourself by presenting God’s love wherever you go. Thomas’ example and sacrifice are one of the thousandths that have and are going to lay down their lives for the Catholic faith. Their sacrifice is an official call for those of the to-day and sacrifice and find themselves within God and his people.
Aquinas made an enormous effort to make logic and religion work together, ultimately choosing to drop his logical writing and commit himself to pursuing salvation. Aquinas’s efforts to link logic and his religion parallel today’s continued efforts to force religion into the sciences or to attempt the reverse. But his struggle also acted as a direct view into medieval western Christian culture; the western Christians repeatedly encountered problems in the academic realm with fitting Christianity and higher thinking together which, would occur for far longer than Aquinas’s time. But, if one looks at the struggle in less educated groups it mirrors Aquinas’s except, rather than fitting logic and religion together there is an effort to combine religions or religion and superstition together. Second to Aquinas as an example for religion’s effect was what I discovered whilst researching my presentation topic. I had been under the impression that, as in modern times, the medical focus would be anatomical or chemical. However, as most aspects of medieval culture are, the world of medicine was focused on the spirit. This spiritual focus remained through the middle ages and was catered to by humourism, astrology, and Christianity. While medicine’s focus did indeed limit it in some ways on a physical level, there were still great
Catherine of Siena. The Dialogue of the Divine Providence . Trans. Algar Thorold. 1907. 25 Feb. 2004 .
In the above essay, I analyzed Aquinas’s efficient cause argument and presented Russell’s objections to some of the claims that Aquinas made. I then showed how Russell’s objection failed based mainly on the fact that the first cause is something that is unchanging. This, in turn, supported Aquinas’s argument for the existence of God.
While I do agree with some of Aquinas’ claims. Such as the idea that nothing comes from nothing. I believe something has to happen to become. It could be the efficient cause, causing the world to start. Although still having the question what made such a cause to effect everything in the
Spoto, D. (2002). The Reluctant Saint: The life of Francis of Assisi. New York: Penguin Group.
Aquinas begins one of his arguments for the purpose of knowledge by distinguishing two types of perfection, existence and “perfection belonging to one thing is found in another” (Aquinas, q.2 a. 2) essentially, knowledge. In the first type of perfection, existence, something would be perfect according to its own species. The species, or forms, are perfect from the act of their existence. There are four forms: human, animal, plant and inanimate; each of these are perfect in their existence. Since each species has its own perfection, “the perfect falls short of absolute perfection to the extent that perfection is found in other species” (Aquinas De veritate q.2,a.2), meaning that no form can hold absolute perfection. In this definition of knowledge where knowing conforms to being, an acorn, for example, is perfect when it can grow, reproduce and nourish, reaching its final cause. But it is only the perfection of an oak tree (plant). The oak tree cannot have the perfection of a human. Perfection is limited to each individual form, because the whole of perfection is more perfect than the perfection of each
1) Oxford Readings in Philosophy. The Concept of God. New York: Oxford University press 1987
Emery, G. (2007). The Trinitarian Theology of Saint Thomas Aquinas. New York, New York: Oxford University Press Inc.
Thomas Aquinas uses five proofs to argue for God’s existence. A few follow the same basic logic: without a cause, there can be no effect. He calls the cause God and believes the effect is the world’s existence. The last two discuss what necessarily exists in the world, which we do not already know. These things he also calls God.
Pollen, John Hungerford. "St. Ignatius Loyola." The Catholic Encyclopedia. Vol. 7. New York: Robert Appleton Company,1910. 23 Mar. 2014 .
Ullmann, Walter. A Short History of the Papacy in the Middle Ages. 2nd ed. New York City, NY: Routledge, 2003.