Wait a second!
More handpicked essays just for you.
More handpicked essays just for you.
Euthyphro's dilemma essay
Socrates impact on greek philosophy
Socrates impact on greek philosophy
Don’t take our word for it - see why 10 million students trust us with their essay needs.
This philosophical study will define the relationship between morality and religion in the Socratic dialogue of the Euthyphro by Plato. The primary argument put forth by Socrates is to determine the causality of morality/piousness in and unto itself or by the approval of the gods. Socrates attempts to question the moral and religious authority of Euthyphro, which defines the important originations of the “moral good” through the command of the gods. However, Socrates defines the original presence of the morality/piousness before the gods can “approve” or disapprove” of its goodness. This is the theoretical position of denying the issue of "divine command” of the gods’ existence before morality/piousness, which Socrates refutes in the arguments …show more content…
of Euthyphro. In essence, the problem of “divine command” will be analyzed to define the relationship of the “moral good” and the role of gods in the Euthyphro by Plato. The relationship between the “moral good” and religion is an issue of causality when determining which comes first in defining what is “pious” in the dialogue between Socrates and Euthyphro. In this debate, the originations of the “moral good” are defined by the piousness of the gods as a form of approval as a religious conviction on the part of Euthyphro. In this manner, Euthyphro states: I would certainly say that the pious is what all the gods love, and the opposite, which all the gods hate, is the impious” (Plato 173). This statement infers that the gods command moral and pious behavior because they approve of it, which suggests that they wield some type of overarching power to define the rule of moral conduct. However, Socrates views this argument as being erroneous because the a priori existence of the “pious” is not created by the gods, but only approved by the gods: “It is loved then because it is pious, but it is not pious because it is loved” (173). This aspect of the dialogue defines the ambiguity of causality between religion and morality, since it begins to redefine the limitations of the god’s power to “approve” piousness or impiousness as a definition of the moral good. This argument is the platform in which Socrates begins to unravel the relationship between religiosity and moral goodness, which Euthyphro has taken for granted as a theory on divine command. The further development of Euthyphro's assumptions on the approval of the gods expands on the mysteries of piety and the “moral good”, which baffle the younger man. Socrates dispels the notion of the “god-beloved” notion of godly approval by getting Euthyphro to admit the ambiguous relationship between the moral good as a form of piousness and the issue of divine command from the gods. In this manner, the definition of what is pious is put into question because Euthyphro’s argument assumes that piousness is what the gods approve of, instead of defining what is it in and unto itself: If the pious were loved because it was pious, the god-beloved would be loved because it was god-beloved, and if the god-beloved was god-beloved because it was loved by the gods, the pious would also be pious because it was loved by the gods; but now you see that they are in opposite cases as being altogether different from each other (Plato 175). This opposing argument, put forth by Socrates, defines the pre-existing quality of piousness that the gods claim to “love”, but it does not define what piousness is in and unto itself. Therefore, the “moral good”—as defined by piousness—is merely loved by the gods, yet Socrates is making the claim that Euthyphro is merely following religious doctrines, instead of finding what the “moral good” means for himself. In this manner, Socrates challenges Euthyphro to see the contradicting aspects of causality for piousness and divine command, which make this discerning quality in the argument: “”The one [piousness] is of a nature to be loved because it is loved, the other is loved because it is of a nature to be loved” (Plato 173). In this manner, Socrates dissolves Euthyphro’s assumption that he knows the moral good/piousness, since he cannot defined what piousness is in relation to his own re-assumed conviction about the power of divine command through the gods. In this manner, the origins of the “moral good” dispel the notion of the causality of piety through the approval of the gods. In one way, the rejection of a “divine command” argument illustrates Socrates’ attempt to show Euthyphro that morality must be learned by a personal and individual investigation of moral conduct, which does not presume a godly or religious authority that must be followed blindly.
Certainly, Socrates’ arguments about the limitations of godly knowledge of the “moral good” devolve the idea of divine command as a cause of piety, but more importantly, it defines the philosophical evaluation of piety as a way to educate Euthyphro to analyze his pre-assumed beliefs with greater conviction. In this dialogue, the issue of the “moral good” becomes a more complex relationship between Euthyphro’s religious and moral perception of philosophy: “I told you a short while ago, Socrates, that it is a considerable task to acquire any precise knowledge of these things” (177). This new perspective defines the effectiveness of Socrates’ argument to dispel the overly confident assumption that the gods approve of piety, since piety has its own unique qualities that need to be defined. This moral and religious relationship is ambiguous because Socrates has opened the possibility of Euthyphro coming to his own conclusions about the gods and the “moral good”, which should be presumed by religious doctrines or in the divine command of the
gods. In conclusion, the causal relationship between morality and religion has been defined in the dialogue that occurs between Euthyphro and Socrates in the Euthyphro by Plato. The ambiguous definition of piety as a source of the “moral good” is typically defined by Euthyphro's instance that godly approval of piousness/morality is a form of causality. However, Socrates illustrates the greater likelihood that “piety” existed before the gods, since they choose to love it, and therefore, approve of it. More so, Socrates makes no claims of knowing the causal nature of piety or the “moral good”, but he is willing to encourage Euthyphro to make his own conclusions about the originations of these beliefs. This ambiguous dialogue about the relationship of religion and morality is crucial, since Socrates does not want Euthyphro to simply take gods for granted, and to blindly follow the dictates of moral behaviors without questioning their validity as knowledge. These is the important relationship between morality and religion, which is defined by Socrates’ philosophical interrogation of Euthyphro on the questionable causalities of the “moral good” and the role of the gods in dictating these pious behaviors.
During the dialogue, Euthyphro defines, “Piety means prosecuting the unjust individual who has committed murder or sacrilege, or any other such crime, as I am doing now, whether he is your father or mother or whoever he is.” Given this Euthyphro overarching principles can be summarized as divine law requires to prosecute the offender no matter who she or he is. Also, the ideology should be what befits humans as well. Socrates is fine with how Euthyphro accounts the factual evidence of his father’s misguided acts. What Socrates takes problem is how Euthyphro uses greek mythology to highlight that taking action against your parents is the correct direction of action. Due to the fact that mythology isn’t confirmed to be true in any sense, socrates feels as though this is extremely inappropriate. Euthyphro actions should be based on divine law with results in him being impious. Socrates ultimate principles can be summarized as respect for parents should be the ultimate law combined with whatever does not befit the gods shouldn’t befit everyone else. Insert another
Consequently, In Plato's Euthyphro, our acquaintance with Socrates is immensely beneficial to society, as we obtain awareness on such an innovative method of achieving intuition. The Socratic approach is now a fundamental approach implemented in daily conversation in society Furthermore, not only is Socrates is able to verify that the true seekers are the wise; he also validates the notion that the answers to many questions are merely questions. Simply because, life is so debate that certain subjects begin to intertwine. To sum up, Plato's Euthyphro is extremely indicative of this Socratic irony, for the reason being that: Socrates's portrays a sense of intellectual humility.
When discussing specific knowledge, it is often hard to pin down an exact definition of what it is you are discussing. Often a concept or word will get thrown around so often that it will begin to be taken for granted and when pressed, a person may struggle to pin down specifically what it is they mean. Realizing this, Socrates often went out and attempted to fix these kinds of problems and find out what people actually knew, compared to what they just thought they knew. In the dialogues Euthyphro and Meno, Socrates attempts to pin down definitions for piety and virtue, respectively. In doing so, we are shown that the thinkers in question struggle to define these terms, and attempt to do so in vague terms that may vary heavily under different circumstances. What Socrates is attempting to find is one definitive definition of piety and virtue, what is called his One Form Requirement. Rather than defining something by classifying different parts that make it up, Socrates maintains the belief that piety and virtue both can be simplified into one specific form that describes exactly what makes all F actions F.
Euthyphro’s second definition of piety is “the pious is what the gods love”. Socrates takes this idea and
In the Euthyphro, Socrates is making his way into the courthouse; however, prior to entering he had a discussion with a young priest of Athens, Euthyphro. This dialogue relates religion and justice to one another and the manner in which they correlate. Euthyphro feels as though justice necessitates religion and Socrates feels the opposite, religion necessitates justice. Euthyphro claims that religion is everything, justice, habits, traditions, customs, cultures, etc. all are derived from religion. Socrates went on to question what exactly would be the definition of pious. Euthyphro offered Socrates three definitions of pious and in all three Socrates was able to successfully find fault...
There are times in every mans life where our actions and beliefs collide—these collisions are known as contradictions. There are endless instances in which we are so determined to make a point that we resort to using absurd overstatements, demeaning language, and false accusations in our arguments. This tendency to contradict ourselves often questions our character and morals. Similarly, in The Trial of Socrates (Plato’s Apology), Meletus’ fallacies in reason and his eventual mistake of contradicting himself will clear the accusations placed on Socrates. In this paper, I will argue that Socrates is not guilty of corrupting the youth with the idea of not believing in the Gods but of teaching the youth to think for themselves by looking to new divinities.
Keeping true to Socratic/Platonic methodology, questions are raised in the Euthyphro by conversation; specifically “What is holiness?” After some useless deliberation, the discussion between Socrates and Euthyphro ends inconclusively. Euthyphro varying definitions of piety include “What I do is pious to the gods,” and, “What is pleasing to the gods is pious.” Socrates proves these definitions to be insufficient, which leads us to the Apology.
Dating all the way back to ancient Greece, Plato raised a challenge by merely asking, “Is it right because God commands it, or does God command it because it’s right?” Nowadays, this simple yet complex question poses a problem to modern day Christians. When understanding this question, you are forced to believe you only have one of two choices to accept. Those being either it is right because God commands it or God commands it because it is right. If it is right because God commands it then anything, specifically evil, could be right. On the other hand, if God commands it because it is right then the standard of goodness is no longer. Both options are hostile to Christianity. However, after further investigation, there is a third option: God’s very nature is the standard of goodness. By closely examining Plato’s Euthyphro Dilemma, it’s clear that a theist should undoubtedly accept the third option, being that of God’s nature is the standard of goodness.
The story that is found in Plato’s dialogue Euthyphro proposes a dilemma that has since been a very controversial subject. When Socrates encounters Euthyphyo, he is on his way to trail to face charges against his own father. His father had been accused o...
In this paper I will discuss the Divine Command Theory (DCT) and its attracted features. I will also discuss the problems proposed by Plato’s writing known as “The Euthypro Problem” (EP). Using the Euthypro Problem I plan to show how Divine Command Theory makes morality arbitrary and God’s goodness meaningless. First I will begin by clearly defining the Divine Command Theory. I will then proceed to discuss the attractive features of the Divine Command Theory. After I will discus “The Euthypro Problem” and its argument against the Divine Command Theory. Lastly I will discuss the results of Divine Command Theory and its effects on believers of God.
Euthyphro was arguing that by doing what the gods believe is holy and pious you are making them better, in other words you are taking care of them and it is like a kind of service that you are doing towards the gods. Euthyphro said, “The kind of care, Socrates, that slaves take of their masters” which meant that you are taking care of them in the sense that you are making them better and not actually caring for them (17, 13d). In other words, you are helping improve them and this is a service that the gods appreciate and want you to do. He believed that this service is improving the gods and that they like this service. The gods believe that being holy is a service towards them, therefore there should be a reason on why the gods use us and want to reward our holiness. He believes that the gods choose what is holy for a reason and should be approved by
In The Euthyphro, Socrates uses his Socratic Method to disprove the Divine Command theory to his friend, Euthyphro. According to the textbook, the Socratic Method is a method that Socrates would use to get to the foundation of his students beliefs. He would ask continual questions about a student’s belief or assumption until a contradiction was raised. By doing so, Socrates would force his students to question their own beliefs and truly discern why they believed them. Socrates applied this method to Euthyphro when Socrates and Euthyphro had a conversation in regards to the definition of holiness. During this conversation, Euthyphro states that holiness is what is agreeable to the gods. However, Socrates disputes this idea by stating that gods quarrel just as humans quarrel in regards to issues such as right and wrong, holy and unholy, and justice and injustice. With this reasoning, Socrates argues that what one god may view as right or moral, another god may view as wrong or immoral. Thus, an action may be acceptable and moral to one god and unacceptable and immoral to another, and what is considered to
The nature of morality is believed to have been heavily impacted by the enduring history of religion, yet philosophical conflict has arisen of over differing interpretations of Socrates question of whether ‘our moral virtues were designed as good by an omnipotent God, or whether they are good because God recognizes them as good.’
world, so one would never be sure that one has accomplished without a doubt the highest standard of morals. In his discourse Euthyphro, Plato considered the proposal that it is divine approval that makes an activity decent. ‘Plato pointed out that if this were the case, we could not say that the gods approve of the actions because the actions are good. Why then do the gods approve of these actions rather than others? Is their approval entirely arbitrary?’ (Sofroniou, p12). Plato considered this incomprehensible thus held that there must be a few gauges of right or wrong that are free of the preferences and abhorrence of the divine beings. The third view holds that ‘all knowledge is relative to the individual, in which case there cannot be absolute morality: all ethics are relative to circumstances, people and cultures’ (Brackman). What can be drawn from this view is that it is tricky in light of the fact that, taken to its conclusion, there is no such thing as ethics by any stretch of the imagination. The following section will look at why as human’s do we act ethically.
The interesting dialogue between Socrates and Euthyphro demonstrates this Socratic method of questioning in order to gain a succinct definition of a particular idea, such as piety. Though the two men do not come to a conclusion about the topic in the conversation seen in Euthyphro, they do discover that piety is a form of justice, which is more of a definition than their previous one. Their conversation also helps the reader to decipher what makes a good definition. Whenever Euthyphro attempts to define piety, Socrates seems to have some argument against the idea. Each definition offered, therefore, becomes more succinct and comes closer to the actual concept of piety, rather than just giving an example or characteristic of it. To be able to distinguish between a good definition and a bad one is the first step to defining what Socrates so desperately wished to define: w...