Wait a second!
More handpicked essays just for you.
More handpicked essays just for you.
Stuart Mill's utilitarianism
Controversial topics between religion and morality
Utilitarianism john stuart mill essay
Don’t take our word for it - see why 10 million students trust us with their essay needs.
Recommended: Stuart Mill's utilitarianism
John Stuart Mill, Patrick Devlin, H.L.A Hart, and Ronald Dworkin each provide varying views on what constitutes morality and what the role of society/the law should be in protecting morality. The discussion of these four philosophers provides insight into this debate, as each philosopher provides a different perspective. For example, Mill being a utilitarian gives him a unique view. I will discuss Mill, Devlin, Hart, and Dworkin and compare their views in order to gain a better understanding of what constitutes morality and how far should society and the law be permitted to interact with morality.
Mill’s harm principle states that the law can only coerce its citizens to act differently, if the action in question is harming others. If an individual's
…show more content…
action does not harm others, the law cannot intervene. For example, if William does drugs in his apartment, by himself there is no evidence that he is harming anyone else, therefore the law cannot use its coercive power to persuade William to abstain from taking the drugs. Mill argues for this by appealing to an epistemological argument: an individual has epistemological access to themselves that the law does not, thus individuals are the best judge for what is good for them. Society does not have the knowledge of an individual’s tastes and pursuits, without this understanding a society cannot intervene and tell individuals what is best for them. The law does not have an epistemological access to one’s thoughts and desires, only that individual possess that, thus they are the best judge of what is right for him/her. He also contends that using coercion on actions that only harm the individual has long term adverse effects. expand. Although Mill is a utilitarian it is important to note that even if one were to reject the principle of utility, which is that an action is right if it maximizes happiness (as pleasure is qualitative) and an action is wrong if it produces pain, if you value political liberty as a primary good then you will accept the harm principle. The reason being is that the harm principle does not infringe upon people's political liberty, because it states legal coercion is only justifiable if someone’s action is harming others. Locke, who is not a utilitarian, would appeal to the harm principle because it is the best way to ensure an individual’s liberty is protected. It is important to note that one’s behavior causes harm when it violates a duty one has to others. For example, someone drunk driving is harmful to others because it puts other people's lives in danger. According to the harm principle it is justifiable for the government to intervene in this instance because others lives are in danger and only in these types of instances. Thus, the harm principle protects one’s political liberty by preventing it from being violated. Devlin’s disintegration thesis contrasts Mill’s harm principle in that the disintegration thesis contends that a society has a right to enforce compliance with its moral code. As a society is a group of people with shared ideas about politics and morality. Devlin asserts that immorality threatens a society’s beliefs on morality in the same way that treason threatens its thoughts on politics. Treason and immorality are analogous for this reason. It is justified to prevent and punish treason because treason threatens political ideas in the same way that deviant actions threaten morality, therefore it is justified to prevent immorality. The thesis asserts that the enforcement of morality is justified on the grounds that the failure to do so will cause the society to disintegrate. This contrasts the harm principle because Devlin’s thesis warrants a society to enforce morality, while the harm principle restricts the enforcement of morality only when dealing with actions that infringe upon the rights/safety of others. The disintegration thesis presents society with the right to go after immorality because if it did not that society would disintegrate. Hart’s critique of the disintegration thesis is that it essentially is the conservative thesis, which states that if society does not enforce morality then that society will lose its distinction, namely it will not be the same.
Hart states that there is no empirical evidence to support that society would disintegrate and become a Hobbesian state of nature, if morality was not enforced by the law. He asserts that when you press supporters of the disintegration thesis for evidence that society would revert back to a Hobbesian state, their response is much more like the conservative thesis: that the society will not look the same. For example, if homosexuality were allowed in Kansas, then that society will lose its distinction because it would not really look like Kansas anymore it would be more like San Francisco. There is no evidence that Kansas would disintegrate and its society would regress to a Hobbesian state. This illustrates Hart’s point that there is no empirical evidence to support the disintegration thesis, rather supporters of this thesis give reasons that support the conservative thesis, not empirical evidence to support that society would disintegrate without the enforcement of morality. He contends that it is not the disintegration thesis if society just loses its distinction, thus justifying his claim that there is no empirical evidence for the disintegration
thesis. The difference between the disintegration thesis and the conservative thesis, as mentioned earlier, is that the disintegration thesis maintains that without the enforcement of morality society will disintegrate. While, the conservative thesis does not contend that society will disintegrate without the enforcement of morality, only that society will lose its distinction and not look the same. Hart describes the disintegration thesis as: “the case for the enforcement of morality on this view is that its maintenance is necessary to prevent the disintegration of society” (1). This contrasts the conservative thesis as it does not state that society would disintegrate only that it would lose its distinction. Devlin’s view on what counts as morality rests on what they reasonable man believes to be immoral, largely based on their feeling. Dworkin discusses this view and states that “if it happens however, that the vast bulk of the community is agreed upon an answer, even though a small minority of educated men may dissent, the legislator has a duty to act on the consensus” (5). The two reasons being that “the decision must rest on some article of moral faith” and that in a democracy issues like these would have to be settled with a democratic consensus. The second reason is that “the community must take the moral responsibility, and it must therefore act on its own light-that is on the moral faith of its members” (5). These reasons support Devlin’s view that moral judgements should be based upon what a reasonable person would accept and that the court should follow the moral consensus of the majority, rather than a few elitist citizens. Dworkin rejects Devlin’s view of what counts as morality. Devlin believes that what the counts for morality is the judgment of a reasonable person, not necessarily the rational person. The judgment that counts for morality can be a matter of feeling. For Devlin intolerance, indignation, and disgust are sufficient for morality. Dworkin rejects this premise and states that disgust is not the wrong making feature, rather the wrong making feature is what makes the person disgusted in the first place. According to Dworkin, judgments can be made in a discriminatory and non discriminatory sense. With the discriminatory sense, one is discriminating between the good and the bad and must provide reasons for his/her judgment. Not all reasons count as justification, such as prejudices or religion. However in a non discriminatory sense one is not expected to provide reasons or be rational, and he/she can base their judgments on feeling. This looks like the sort of thing Devlin is appealing to, which Dworkin rejects. Dworkin states that one should be able to give reasons for their judgement to ensure they are not based on prejudices and are justifiable, thus when discussing morality a society should appeal to a discriminatory sense.
Morality derives from the Latin moralitas meaning, “manner, character, or proper behavior.” In light of this translation, the definition invites the question of what composes “proper behavior” and who defines morality through these behaviors, whether that be God, humanity, or an amalgamation of both. Socrates confronted the moral dilemma in his discourses millennia ago, Plato refined his concepts in his Republic, and leaders such as Mahatma Gandhi would commit their life work to defining and applying the term to political reform. Finally, after so many years, Martin Luther King’s “A Letter from Birmingham Jail” reaches a consensus on the definition of morality, one that weighs the concepts of justice and injustice to describe morality as the
Kittelson, James M. Luther the Reformer: The Story of the Man and His Career. Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 2003.
From top to bottom, John Stuart Mill put forth an incredible essay depicting the various unknown complexities of morality. He has a remarkable understanding and appreciation of utilitarianism and throughout the essay the audience can grasp a clearer understanding of morality. Morality, itself, may never be totally defined, but despite the struggle and lack of definition it still has meaning. Moral instinct comes differently to everyone making it incredibly difficult to discover a basis of morality. Society may never effectively establish the basis, but Mill’s essay provides people with a good idea.
In order for the insistence that equity and impartiality to hold true to Mill's Utility, we must find a foundation from within his argumentation that will support it. Thus we turn to Mill's sanctions, or incentives that he proposes to drive one towards the path of Utility. Mill's first sanction, the internal sanction, leads one to act ethically because of the fear of displeasure that might arise from other people if one does not act in this manner. Mill justifies that individuals desire the warmness of others as an incentive to acting unselfishly in the attempt to acquire the greatest good, and fear the dissatisfaction of others. Mill's second sanction, the internal sanction, is in essence an individual's inner conscience. With the assumption that the conscience is pure and free from corruption, Mill implies that satisfaction is brought forth to the conscience when one successfully and ethically commits to one's duties, the duty of Utility. What is undesired is the feeling of dissatisfaction that spawns when one does not act dutifully. In order for this rationale to make sense, one must do what is almost unavoid...
Thesis statement: Martin Luther was responsible for the break-up of the Catholic Church Martin Luther was a representative during the 16th century of a desire widespread of the renewal and reform of the Catholic Church. He launched the Protestant reform a continuation of the medieval religious search. From the Middle ages, the church faced many problems such as the Babylonian Captivity and the Great Schism that hurt the prestige of the church. Most of the clergy lived in great luxury while most people were poor and they set an immoral example. The clergy had low education and many of them didn’t attend their offices.
Pojman, L. (2002). 6: Utilitarianism. Ethics: discovering right and wrong (pp. 104-113). Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.
Mill, John Stewart. "Utilitarianism: John Stewart Mill." Fifty Readings Plus: An Introduction to Philosophy. Ed. Donald C. Abel. Boston, MA: McGraw-Hill, 2004. 416-25. Print.
The harm principle was published in Mill’s work Of Liberty in 1859. He states, “That the only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others. His own good, either physical or moral, is not a sufficient warrant (978).” This means that government is not able to control peoples’ actions unless they are causing harm to other individuals. He also states that if you are causing harm to yourself the government shall not involve themselves. Different forms of harm are applicable, such as physical harm, property damage and emotional harm. Mill also explains that harm, in whatever form to others, can be the result of an action or the result of inaction. Both of these are a violation to the harm principle and the government has the right to step in; it does not matter whether harm was caused by the result of your action or inaction to the situation. The harm principle’s purpose is to be able to only let government interfere with human society when one is causi...
Cahn, Steven M., and Peter J. Markie. "John Stuart Mill's Utilitarianism; Chapter 2: What Utilitarianism Is." 2009. Ethics: History, Theory, and Contemporary Issues. 4th ed. New York: Oxford UP, 2009. 330-41. Print.
Kant’s moral philosophy is very direct in its justification of human rights, especially the ideals of moral autonomy and equality as applied to rational human beings. John Stuart Mills’ theory of utilitarianism also forms a solid basis for human rights, especially his belief that utility is the supreme criterion for judging morality, with justice being subordinate to it. The paper looks at how the two philosophers qualify their teachings as the origins of human rights, and comes to the conclusion that the moral philosophy of Kant is better than that of Mills. Emmanuel Kant Kant’s moral philosophy is built around the formal principles of ethics rather than substantive human goods. He begins by outlining the principles of reasoning that can be equally expected of all rational persons, regardless of their individual desires or partial interests.
In his essay, Utilitarianism Mill elaborates on Utilitarianism as a moral theory and responds to misconceptions about it. Utilitarianism, in Mill’s words, is the view that »actions are right in proportion as they tend to promote happiness, wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness.«1 In that way, Utilitarianism offers an answer to the fundamental question Ethics is concerned about: ‘How should one live?’ or ‘What is the good or right way to live?’.
Harman, G. (2000). Is there a single true morality?. Explaining value and other essays in moral philosophy (pp. 77-99). Oxford: Clarendon Press ;.
In this paper, I will thoroughly discuss the theory of Utilitarianism. I will discuss fundamental principles of the theory, Rachels’ definition of morally right actions based on the theory, as well as John Stuart Mill’s definition of morally right actions. I will also discuss the arguments against the theory due to fictional situations and the conflict it possess with justice. First I will define the theory of Utilitarianism and it’s fundamental principles. Then I will state Rachels’ and Mills’ definition of morally right actions. I will then discuss the arguments against the theory of Utilitarianism that prove utilitarianism as incompatible and conflicting with the demands of justice. Then I will discuss the difference between Rule-Utilitarianism and Act-Utilitarianism. Using the two I will discuss how Rachels’ fictional situation of justice applies to both.
David Hume and Immanuel Kant each made a significant break from other theorists in putting forward a morality that doesn’t require a higher being or god, for a man to recognize his moral duty. Although Hume and Kant shared some basic principals they differed on their view of morality. In comparing the different views on human will and the maxims established to determine moral worth by David Hume and Immanuel Kant, I find their theories on morality have some merit although limited in view.
John Stuart Mill’s theory on his harm principal can be well supportive since harm is not subjected, contrary, throughout almost all cultures, harm is classified the same. We can see this through laws and punishments that countries have with regards to harm. For example, harm is defined by the Canadian Government as “hurt or injury to a person that interferes with the health or comfort of the person and that is more than merely transient or trifling in nature” (Criminal Code R.S.C., 1985, C. c-46). Similar to the definition given by Australian law harm is “any hurt or injury, which doesn’t necessarily have to be permanent, but must more than “merely transient and trifling” (R v. Donovan 1934 KB 498). These two countries are on opposite sides of the world and have very contrasting cultures – nevertheless, when it comes to harm, their regulations are almost identical. This proves that Mill’s harm theory can be defended since there is evident that countries have the same interpretation, thus is theory can be rightfully put in place.