Wait a second!
More handpicked essays just for you.
More handpicked essays just for you.
Piety in plato works
Ancient greek view of the gods
Ancient greek view of the gods
Don’t take our word for it - see why 10 million students trust us with their essay needs.
Recommended: Piety in plato works
In this section of Euthyphro, a dialogue recounted by Plato, Socrates is urging Euthyphro to define piety. When Euthyphro first explains piety, he names characteristics that exemplify it, but Socrates’ expects a fundamentally sound definition. Euthyphro proposes that “what’s loved by the gods is pious, and what’s not loved by the gods is impious” (Euthyphro, 7a). However, Socrates is not impressed with this definition because it’s ambiguous and dismisses the differences in the gods’ opinions.
Euthyphro was a religious intellectual, so he should’ve been able to define piety. However, Socrates wanted to show Euthyphro that he wasn’t as knowledgeable as he thought. Socrates knew beforehand that Euthyphro wouldn’t be able to give a sound definition, or standard, for what is pious, so this dialogue is a reflection on Euthyphro’s reasoning.
…show more content…
Once Euthyphro gave Socrates his definition of piety, Socrates starts questioning the logic of the definition.
Since there are a plethora of Greek gods, Socrates argues that “a thing that’s god-loved is, it seems, also god-hated” (Euthyphro, 8b) because “the gods quarrel and differ with one another, and there’s mutual hostility among them” (Euthyphro, 7b) even about what’s just or unjust. Socrates gives an example of disagreement between gods to emphasize how Euthyphro’s definition is insufficient: “what you’re [Euthyphro] now doing in prosecuting your father was something pleasing to Zeus but displeasing to Cronus and Uranus… and similarly for any other gods who may differ from one another on the matter” (Euthyphro, 8b). Socrates ultimately berates Euthyphro’s definition of piety and rejects it because it’s inaccurate.
Socrates, who’s indicted for being impious, is leading Euthyphro, the self-proclaimed intellectual, to note that he is not all-knowing and that his definition of piety is flawed and has no fundamental
basis.
During the dialogue, Euthyphro defines, “Piety means prosecuting the unjust individual who has committed murder or sacrilege, or any other such crime, as I am doing now, whether he is your father or mother or whoever he is.” Given this Euthyphro overarching principles can be summarized as divine law requires to prosecute the offender no matter who she or he is. Also, the ideology should be what befits humans as well. Socrates is fine with how Euthyphro accounts the factual evidence of his father’s misguided acts. What Socrates takes problem is how Euthyphro uses greek mythology to highlight that taking action against your parents is the correct direction of action. Due to the fact that mythology isn’t confirmed to be true in any sense, socrates feels as though this is extremely inappropriate. Euthyphro actions should be based on divine law with results in him being impious. Socrates ultimate principles can be summarized as respect for parents should be the ultimate law combined with whatever does not befit the gods shouldn’t befit everyone else. Insert another
Consequently, In Plato's Euthyphro, our acquaintance with Socrates is immensely beneficial to society, as we obtain awareness on such an innovative method of achieving intuition. The Socratic approach is now a fundamental approach implemented in daily conversation in society Furthermore, not only is Socrates is able to verify that the true seekers are the wise; he also validates the notion that the answers to many questions are merely questions. Simply because, life is so debate that certain subjects begin to intertwine. To sum up, Plato's Euthyphro is extremely indicative of this Socratic irony, for the reason being that: Socrates's portrays a sense of intellectual humility.
A question that breaks off from that is, “Is the pious being loved by the gods because it is pious, or is it pious because it is being loved by the gods (10a)?” Without reading Euthyphro, understanding this question would be nearly impossible. I think that the answer requires a lot of thinking. Piety is pious simply because it is a pious thing, not because it is loved. If you take gods out of the scenario, piety is based on societal beliefs, pious actions are done to please ourselves, and we already have the knowledge to make pious things. Socrates was not found guilty of being impious, but he was found guilty for not believing the same way his society did, showing that piety is linked with society, not the
When discussing specific knowledge, it is often hard to pin down an exact definition of what it is you are discussing. Often a concept or word will get thrown around so often that it will begin to be taken for granted and when pressed, a person may struggle to pin down specifically what it is they mean. Realizing this, Socrates often went out and attempted to fix these kinds of problems and find out what people actually knew, compared to what they just thought they knew. In the dialogues Euthyphro and Meno, Socrates attempts to pin down definitions for piety and virtue, respectively. In doing so, we are shown that the thinkers in question struggle to define these terms, and attempt to do so in vague terms that may vary heavily under different circumstances. What Socrates is attempting to find is one definitive definition of piety and virtue, what is called his One Form Requirement. Rather than defining something by classifying different parts that make it up, Socrates maintains the belief that piety and virtue both can be simplified into one specific form that describes exactly what makes all F actions F.
Euthyphro’s second definition of piety is “the pious is what the gods love”. Socrates takes this idea and
In the Euthyphro, Socrates is making his way into the courthouse; however, prior to entering he had a discussion with a young priest of Athens, Euthyphro. This dialogue relates religion and justice to one another and the manner in which they correlate. Euthyphro feels as though justice necessitates religion and Socrates feels the opposite, religion necessitates justice. Euthyphro claims that religion is everything, justice, habits, traditions, customs, cultures, etc. all are derived from religion. Socrates went on to question what exactly would be the definition of pious. Euthyphro offered Socrates three definitions of pious and in all three Socrates was able to successfully find fault...
There are times in every mans life where our actions and beliefs collide—these collisions are known as contradictions. There are endless instances in which we are so determined to make a point that we resort to using absurd overstatements, demeaning language, and false accusations in our arguments. This tendency to contradict ourselves often questions our character and morals. Similarly, in The Trial of Socrates (Plato’s Apology), Meletus’ fallacies in reason and his eventual mistake of contradicting himself will clear the accusations placed on Socrates. In this paper, I will argue that Socrates is not guilty of corrupting the youth with the idea of not believing in the Gods but of teaching the youth to think for themselves by looking to new divinities.
Keeping true to Socratic/Platonic methodology, questions are raised in the Euthyphro by conversation; specifically “What is holiness?” After some useless deliberation, the discussion between Socrates and Euthyphro ends inconclusively. Euthyphro varying definitions of piety include “What I do is pious to the gods,” and, “What is pleasing to the gods is pious.” Socrates proves these definitions to be insufficient, which leads us to the Apology.
The first objection that Socrates stated was that Euthyphro’s first definition of piety was not a definition because it did not express a general idea of the word piety. Soon after the first try at defining the word piety, Euthyphro said that “what is dear to all the gods.” In disagreement, Socrates let out his second objection, which was that some gods could disagree. Then, Euthyphro said that piety was “what is dear to all the gods.” As his final objection, Socrates states “should something be pious just because it is dear to the gods or is it dear to the gods because it is pious?” In short, is an action considered morally right by God because it is morally good, or is it morally good because God orders it? Even though this important point impacts the Divine Command Theory mainly, it also works against the theory of Cultural Relativism. The theory’s problems start arising when you start to think “why do our actions become moral if society or our culture approves of them?” There is also nothing in the theory of Cultural Relativism that explains why normal behavior in a society is considered the moral behavior instead of the other way around. Thus, morality is decided on a random basis there is nothing that says what makes normal behavior moral. The Divine Command Theory and Cultural Relativism both share this weakness that discredits
The story that is found in Plato’s dialogue Euthyphro proposes a dilemma that has since been a very controversial subject. When Socrates encounters Euthyphyo, he is on his way to trail to face charges against his own father. His father had been accused o...
Euthyphro was arguing that by doing what the gods believe is holy and pious you are making them better, in other words you are taking care of them and it is like a kind of service that you are doing towards the gods. Euthyphro said, “The kind of care, Socrates, that slaves take of their masters” which meant that you are taking care of them in the sense that you are making them better and not actually caring for them (17, 13d). In other words, you are helping improve them and this is a service that the gods appreciate and want you to do. He believed that this service is improving the gods and that they like this service. The gods believe that being holy is a service towards them, therefore there should be a reason on why the gods use us and want to reward our holiness. He believes that the gods choose what is holy for a reason and should be approved by
The pious is pious because the gods love it, not the other way around. Plato’s Euthyphro deals with the key philosophical question, “Is the pious being loved by the gods because it is pious, or is it pious because it is being loved by the gods?” Socrates delves on the question because he wants Euthyphro to be aware that he does not know what piety and impiety are. He wants the priest to acknowledge that his answers to piety are not true. The pious and impious are interpreted differently for each person. One can never conclude on a single answer. Euthyphro understands the pious in religious terms only. He makes a sacrifice to the gods and is to behave morally.
To begin with, the ancient Greeks explained the creation of the universe, in particular the Earth and its elements, by a system of anthropomorphism in which their gods are human-like and are representatives of these elements. For example, Zeus is the god of heaven while Hades is the underworld lord (Hesiod, p.145). Unlike the Christians’ god who is “flawless”, the ancient Greeks’ divinities are portrayed as humans and are far from perfect. Their gods behave like ordinary people except they are immortal and have supernatural powers. Like any human being, the Greeks’ gods have love, jealousy, sadness, etc. For instance, in Euripides’ Bacchae, Zeus falls in love with Semele, which makes Hera becomes jealous and tries to kill Semele and Dionysus (Euripides, p.209). The Greeks even have a physically imperfect god, Hephaestus. This is to say that the gods’ attitude toward mortals is affected by how people treat them as the Greeks’ gods have emotions like humans.
Piety comes to be understood as a kind of continuum, and Socrates uniquely represents the “sober mean” on this pious continuum (Strauss 52). In other words, Xenophon’s treatment of Socratic piety in the Memorabilia depends specifically upon highlighting the distinctiveness of Socratic pious praxis from extreme positions. Thus, although Xenophon exonerates Socrates he does so only to an extent that brings into focus the uniqueness of Socratic pious praxis. Moreover, Socrates’ sober view –as outlined by the Memorabilia - limits the power of the divine in two main ways. Firstly, it governs resort to piety through resort to reason; one who is truly pious limits his resort to the divine only to asking questions about unknown outcomes. Accordingly, one who is truly pious, will more readily rely on reason to resolve issues that deviate from this former qualification. This claim is in itself problematic because its implementation depends upon the belief in a formulation of the divine that is uniquely rational; it requires the worship of a divine that in itself acknowledges the full potential of human reason, and thereby understands the limited resort to divinity that would inevitably emerge as an outcome of this rationalistic pious praxis. Furthermore, it requires a very fragile distinction; one can ask
The interesting dialogue between Socrates and Euthyphro demonstrates this Socratic method of questioning in order to gain a succinct definition of a particular idea, such as piety. Though the two men do not come to a conclusion about the topic in the conversation seen in Euthyphro, they do discover that piety is a form of justice, which is more of a definition than their previous one. Their conversation also helps the reader to decipher what makes a good definition. Whenever Euthyphro attempts to define piety, Socrates seems to have some argument against the idea. Each definition offered, therefore, becomes more succinct and comes closer to the actual concept of piety, rather than just giving an example or characteristic of it. To be able to distinguish between a good definition and a bad one is the first step to defining what Socrates so desperately wished to define: w...