Wait a second!
More handpicked essays just for you.
More handpicked essays just for you.
Rousseau's contribution to democratic philosophy
Rousseau's contribution to democratic philosophy
Rousseau on liberty
Don’t take our word for it - see why 10 million students trust us with their essay needs.
Recommended: Rousseau's contribution to democratic philosophy
Edmund Burke, as a conservative theorist, claims that England’s preference for restoration over revolution makes the Glorious Revolution more legitimate than the French Revolution. To substantiate this, Burke quips, “We are not the converts of Rousseau…” to hastily dismiss the French philosophe based on his Enlightenment reputation (75). In comparing Rousseau’s conservatism with Burke’s, it’s important to categorize conservative thought into two genera: foundationalism and traditionalism. While foundationalist conservatives believe that there is a distinct, morally correct way to govern, traditionalist conservatives are grounded in the continuity of government for the purpose of stability. While these two categories are reductionistic, the …show more content…
dichotomy is useful to clarify that there are multiple ways to be conservative and introduces two archetypal paradigms within the monolithic label “conservatism.” Rousseau’s traditionalist conservatism is not significant, but his appeals to prudence mimic the foundationalist aspect of Burke’s conservatism. It is clear that Burke makes the same interpretive error as French revolutionaries: while Rousseau does believe the “general will” legitimizes political change, he further theorizes that the general will naturally begets moderation. These unexpected commonalities will elucidate the persistence of political polarization, and the subsequent speculative devaluation of the opposition’s position. Burke and the French revolutionaries’ depiction of Rousseau alike were most likely based upon his views presented in the Discourse on Inequality, most succinctly summarized by “the uprising that ends in the strangulation or the dethronement of a sultan is as lawful an act as those by which he disposed of the lives and goods of his subjects the day before. Force alone maintained him; force alone brings him down” (90). Quotes such as this allow Burke and French revolutionaries alike to miscategorize Rousseau as unequivocally pro-revolution. Rousseau continues in his Social Contract to allude to his conditions for revolution, ideas eventually heralded by the French revolutionaries. Rousseau’s conservative leanings can be understood by observing the commonalities in with Burke’s ideology. Furthermore, analyzing Rousseau’s work, French revolutionaries may have overlooked Rousseau’s moderate-to-conservative views for the sake of effective revolutionary propaganda. For a philosopher so flippantly discredited by Burke, Rousseau believes in a surprisingly similar sort of prudence in regime change. For example, pro-revolutionary propagandists, and years later, Burke, only familiar with Rousseau in the context of his influence on the French revolution, may interpret Rousseau’s claim in the Social Contract “when...the populace institutes a hereditary government… this is not a commitment in its entering. It is a provisional form that gives it the administration, until the populace is pleased to order it otherwise” to mean that the people have the power to shape the government, and part of that power is the right to reform if the current government does not please them (222). This interpretation, without context, seems to imply that governments can and should be reformed whenever there is a rogue dissatisfactory element. However, Rousseau’s next paragraph, situated within a chapter titled “The Means of Preventing Usurpations of the Government,” introduces the idea that revolution warrants moderation and isn’t universally useful, “It is true that these changes are always dangerous, and that the established government should never be touched except when it becomes incompatible with the public good” (Ibid). This demonstrates that Rousseau isn’t categorically pro-revolution, as the revolution must be accompanied by the general will to establish itself as more legitimate than the rule of force. Rousseau’s hesitation to unconditionally endorse revolution gives him a claim to conservatism based on the general will as a foundational principle: if the general will is not revolution, then the revolution is illegitimate. Burke believes that the means for the preservation and stability of a state lie within the territory of conservation and correction.
However, these two terms are not synonyms, and positing them as such creates a false equivalence, despite conservation one meaning to resist change, and correction to change. Despite this tension, both Burke and Rousseau include elements of both conservation and correction. Burke discounts Rousseau, but sounds remarkably similar to Rousseau in his support of revolution, followed by the condition of moderation. Clarifying that revolution would be advisable under some circumstances, Burke “do[es] most heartily wish that France may be animated by a spirit of rational liberty” believing that “a revolution will be the very last resource of the thinking and the good,” but cautioning that “the very idea of the fabrication of a new government is enough to fill us with disgust and horror” (4, 27). Burke further demonstrates his traditionalist views by cautioning, “A state without the means of some change is without the means of its own preservation,” demonstrating that the need for continuity is more significant than a need to respect foundational beliefs (19). Burke further demonstrates his conservatism when he explains the benefit of Britain’s ability to adapt (traditionalism), yet respect foundational principles: “in what we improve we are never wholly new; in what we retain we are never wholly obsolete (30). Burke expresses that he fears change as much as he fears societal
decay. However, Burke’s view that “[Change] not being done at that time is a proof that the nation was of opinion it ought not to be done at any time” is an example of his foundationalist conservatism (16). In this scenario, Burke doesn’t oppose change because of its radical effects, but rather because it would be morally improper to dissent from the country’s foundation. One could believe Burke’s “necessary deviation” as incompatible with his view that societies should conform to the founders’ design. Burke would respond to this criticism that “It is far from impossible to reconcile … the use both of a fixed rule and an occasional deviation: the sacredness of an hereditary principle of succession in our government with a power of change in its application in cases of extreme emergency” (19). Both political theorists share the idea that revolution should be regarded as dangerous, and thus avoided so long as the state isn’t actively harming its citizens.
According to Carl N. Degler, the entire Revolution should be viewed as a conservative change. In “A New Kind of Revolution,” Degler talked about how the new actions taken place by the English had help structure and shape the colonial government. Not only did the colonies lack the affection of their motherland, Britain, they were also taxed unfairly. On the other hand, “The Radicalism of the American Revolution,” by Gordon S. Wood talks about how the American Revolution was a radical movement. His thesis covered how the country was transitioning from monarchy to republic, and now, democracy. The framers wanted to create a free nation where no single person rule. As well as, the people of the nation having the ultimate say so.
In his essay “The American Revolution as a Response to British Corruption”, historian Bernard Bailyn makes the argument that the American Revolution was inherently conservative because its main goal was to preserve what Americans believed to be their traditional rights as English citizens. He argues that the minor infringements on traditional liberties, like the Stamp Act and the royal ban on lifetime tenure of colonial judges (even though Parliament ruled that judges in England should exercise this right), made the Americans fear that they would set a precedent for future greater infringements on their English liberties. To prove this argument, Baliyan quotes famous primary sources, like John Dickinson, Sam Adams, and various colonial rulings.
Locke and Tocqueville were born nearly two hundred years apart from each other. This span of time corresponds to great changes in the European political spectrum, with Locke being born before the English Glorious Revolution (1688) and Tocqueville born after the French Revolution (1789). Much of what Tocqueville and his contemporaries would have written would have taken for granted the innovations to political thought which Locke and his contemporaries would have fostered. Thus, in areas such as the primacy of human self-interest, to the necessity of nominal societal participation in government, to the belief that “freedom cannot be established without morality, nor morality without faith,” our authors share a common ground. It is from this common ground that Locke and Tocqueville most radically depart from one another, beginning with Locke’s conception of
“If we measure the radicalism of revolutions by the degree of social misery or economic deprivation suffered, or by the number of people killed or manor houses burned, then this conventional emphasis on the conservatism of the American Revolution becomes true enough. B...
Edmund Burke was an Irish political theorist and a philosopher who became a leading figure within the conservative party. Burke has now been perceived as the founder of modern conservatism. He was asked upon to write a piece of literature on the French Revolution. It was assumed that as an Englishman, Burke’s words would be positive and supportive. Given that he was a member of the Whig party, and that he supported the Glorious Revolution in England. Contrary to what was presumed of him, Burke was very critical of the French Revolution. He frequently stated that a fast change in society is bad. He believed that if any change to society should occur, it should be very slow and gradual.
The start of the American Revolution, described by Edmund Morgan as, “the shot heard around the world,” was the “Americans’ search for principles” (Bender 63). Although the world’s colonies did not necessarily seek independence much like the Americans, the world’s colonies were nonetheless tired of the “administrative tyranny” being carried out by their colonizers (Bender 75). The American Revolution set a new standard in the colonies, proclaiming that the “rights of Englishmen” should and must be the “rights of man,” which established a new set foundation for the universal rights of man (Bender 63). This revolution spread new ideas of democracy for the colonized world, reshaping people’s expectations on how they should be governed. Bender emphasizes America as challenging “the old, imperial social forms and cultural values” and embracing modern individualism” (Bender 74). Bender shapes the American Revolution as a turning point for national governments. The American Revolution commenced a new trend of pushing out the old and introducing new self-reliant systems of government for the former
The Founding Fathers of the United States relied heavily on many of the principles taught by John Locke. Many of the principles of Locke’s Second Treatise of Government may easily be discovered in the Declaration of Independence with some minor differences in wording and order. Many of the ideas of the proper role of government, as found in the Constitution of the United States, may be discovered in the study of Locke. In order to understand the foundation of the United States, it is vital that one studies Locke. A few ideas from Hume may be found but the real influence was from Locke. Rousseau, on the other hand, had none.
Burke was as a political conservative, but he was a philosophical radical at heart (Bromwich, 2014). He attempted to legitimize America’s quest for independence by voicing his concerns to Parliament. His concerns were rooted in what he saw as beneficial for all parties involved. As a democratic support, Burke
Locke and Rousseau present themselves as two very distinct thinkers. They both use similar terms, but conceptualize them differently to fulfill very different purposes. As such, one ought not be surprised that the two theorists do not understand liberty in the same way. Locke discusses liberty on an individual scale, with personal freedom being guaranteed by laws and institutions created in civil society. By comparison, Rousseau’s conception portrays liberty as an affair of the entire political community, and is best captured by the notion of self-rule. The distinctions, but also the similarities between Locke and Rousseau’s conceptions can be clarified by examining the role of liberty in each theorist’s proposed state of nature and civil society, the concepts with which each theorist associates liberty, and the means of ensuring and safeguarding liberty that each theorist devises.
Puritanism as a religion declined, both by diluting its core beliefs and by losing its members. This phenomenon was at work even in colonial days, at the religion’s height, because it contained destructive characteristics. It devolved into something barely recognizable in the course of a few generations. We can observe that the decline of Puritanism occurred because it bore within itself the seeds of its own destruction.
Absolutism is a political theory giving rulers complete sovereignty. Louis XIV was one of the most popular successful absolute monarchs. He exercised absolute paternal rights of a father on France and his powers were unlimited by church, legislature, or elites. Calling himself the "Sun King" after the God Apollo, he worked to banish feudalism and create a unified state under his absolute power. To illustrate this power he built the Palace at Versailles and created an elaborate, theatrical royal lifestyle. His reign of 72 years, from 1638 to 1715, it is the longest documented reign of any European monarch. To establish absolutism in France Louis XIV used divers strategies including the centralization of the French state, diminishing the nobles' power and oppressing the third estate.
During the late 17th and early 18th century, many European nations such as France and Russia were absolute monarchies. Even countries such as England had kings who at least attempted to implement absolutism. Indeed the concept of absolutism, where the monarch is the unquestionably highest authority and absolute ruler of every element in the realm, is certainly appealing to any sovereign. However, this unrestricted power was abused, and by the end of the 18th century, absolutism was gone. Absolutism failed because the monarchs' mistreatment of the population caused the people to revolt against their rule and policies. There are many factors which caused this discontent. For one, there was a great loss of human lives. Louis XIV of France participated in four wars, while Peter of Russia ruthlessly executed anyone who stood against his will. Secondly, monarchs attempted to change religious beliefs. This was notable in England where rulers such as James II desired to convert the Anglican nation into Catholicism. Finally, the burden of taxation was more than the population could support. France was brought into huge foreign debt, English kings constantly attempted to raise money, and Peter of Russia increased taxes by 550 percent. These are some of the key reasons why absolutism failed in Europe.
The differences between Thomas Paine and Edmund Burke’s assertions on politics revolve around the two men’s views on the necessity of the French Revolution of between 1789 and 1799. Apparently, the social and political upheaval that shook France in the ten years questioned the absolute Monarchial rule of the French Monarch and in turn, sought to destroy the social hierarchies defined by the aristocrats. In other words, power was subject to the lineage in which an individual is born and for that reason, social infrastructures remained rigid with little to no mobility for the low-class citizens. In answer to the changes sought out by the rebelling French communities, Edmund Burke’s release of the “Reflections on
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, and Donald A. Cress. The "On Democracy" - "The 'Republican'" Basic Political Writings. Indianapolis: Hackett Pub., 1987. 179-80.
The two topics, the sublime and the beautiful are very common in romantic poetry and novels. According to Edmund Burke’s essay, On the Sublime and the Beautiful, He explains the opposition of beauty and of sublimity by a physiological theory. Burke made the opposition of pleasure and pain the source of the two aesthetic categories, deriving beauty from pleasure and sublimity from pain. Edmund Burke describes sublime objects as “vast in their dimensions” and beautiful objects as “small and simple objects.” Edmund Burke goes into further detail describing the sublime and the beautiful in his novel. He describes the sublime as the strongest emotion, which the mind is capable of feeling and the beautiful as something little, humble and innocent. Authors such as Marry Shelly, William Wordsworth and Percy Shelly wrote various works infusing the elements of the sublime and the beautiful into their novels or poems. They took Edmund Burke’s explanation of the sublime and the beautiful and created works based upon his descriptions of the sublime and the beautiful.