Wait a second!
More handpicked essays just for you.
More handpicked essays just for you.
Don’t take our word for it - see why 10 million students trust us with their essay needs.
Most people have probably heard the phrase “what works for one person may not work for another.” It turns out that this also applies to preferences in medical care. Because of the advancements in medical ethics, patient care is no longer strictly based on a doctor’s directive. Goldman, a proponent of patient autonomy asserts that medical paternalism is never warranted by setting out two arguments against medical paternalism. The first argument he sets forth is empirical, the other, moral. While Goldman’s stance on the refutation of medical paternalism is strong from a moral standpoint it is not so much on secure on empirical grounds. To understand this further, it is necessary to clarify the two positions Goldman has presented on his refutation …show more content…
of medical paternalism. Before defining the two arguments it is vital to first discuss the definition of harm. Harm is what Goldman presents to drive his point about medical paternalism being unjust. Goldman says that, “a person is harmed when a state of affairs below a certain level on his preference scale is realized rather than going one up” (Goldman 104). According to Goldman, people have a “preference scale.” That scale is associated with their personal likes and dislikes, and is basically what drives them to live their lives as they see fit. Goldman describes harm as a relative notion (105). Simply put, he says that anything that tips the scale closer to an action that one would not deem to be favorable compared to their own personal value scale is considered harmful to them. What is interesting is that a person does not have to know if they are being harmed in order to be harmed. The inconsistency here is that Goldman does not provide a threshold that can be clearly defined. Therefore, there is no way of knowing exactly when that threshold is approached. Goldman describes this as, the empirical theory. The empirical theory also holds that respecting a patient’s rights will not harm the patient. On the moral ground, Goldman says that, “If our primary goal were always to minimize risk to health and life, we should spend our entire federal budget on health-care areas” (107). This, Goldman says, easily demonstrates that the loss of life is not of the utmost importance to some people and not all decisions we make are based off of what will keep us alive longer, but rather, it is the quality of life that matters. Additionally, depending on person’s situation, health and living might not be as appealing as others would perceive it to be (105). Here, there are many factors to consider, such as, the quality of life, financial status, and an assortment of other factors-- each changing from patient to patient. Again, we would have to take into consideration the patient’s desires. Yet again, this is an issue that Goldman says we cannot make assumptions about because we cannot fathom what the patient perceives to be a life worth living. Ironically, it is this, respecting the patient’s rights, that may actually harm the patient. Which, in this case, Goldman says is okay because the patient has chosen this for himself. This harm can play out in a number of ways. Take for example, a cancer patient who is unwilling to go through a treatment that may or may not work, we can assume the patient’s doctor has disclosed the fact that the treatment itself could be life altering resulting in a number of negative side effects. Given this information, and after weighing options, the patient decides to forego treatment altogether in order to live out the rest of their life as comfortable as possible. This, Goldman explains, is the right of the patient to choose for himself the course of his medical care, and one that needs to and in this case, has been protected. No matter the outcome the patient remains autonomous and the doctor, regardless of what his position is, has no right to interfere with this decision. Therefore, the patient’s right to self-determination has been protected. Goldman claims that not respecting the patient’s autonomy or giving them the opportunity to make their own decisions ultimately harms them further. An example of this is a when a doctor makes the recommendations but conveniently leaves out other alternatives that could sway a patient’s decision from the doctor’s preferred recommendation. The foundation of Goldman’s moral argument is that harm is harmful all the time especially if it prohibits the development or hinders the ability of a person to make decisions. A general thing to consider here is that, if we could live with the same actions being taken against us, or have a decision made for us without disputing it then it would be acceptable. But because each person values things in different ways Goldman says that paternalism can never morally be sanctioned. On the refutation of medical paternalism, Goldman’s claim on moral grounds seems strong. His stance that it is wrong to obstruct in any way the autonomy of a person who is fully capable of making decisions for themselves makes sense. Yet, Goldman has not considered that not all people are capable of autonomy. Think of the intellectually challenged, elderly people with deteriorating conditions such as dementia, or even a person who suffers from a traumatic brain injury. These cases are extreme examples but very realistic realities for some individuals and their families. No matter how we look at it decisions regarding health care for patients in this capacity will eventually require a doctor to intervene to do what is best for the patient in the long run. Ultimately, this is what creates a fallacy on the moral end of Goldman’s argument. This also shows why it is important to consider the argument that paternalism is sometimes justified. In closing, Goldman’s argument against medical paternalism presents two core things, one is that a patient has the right to know and take part in decisions regarding his own medical care regardless of the outcome and the other is ensuring that this right is not infringed upon in any way by health care providers.
“ Personal autonomy over important decisions in one’s life, the ability to attempt to realize one’s own value ordering, is indeed so important that normally no amount of other goods pleasures or avoidance of personal evils can take precedence.” The ultimate goal here is for the patient to remain autonomous. Contrary to what physicians thought of patients in the past, most patients today do want to know the status of their health, and can use this information to live their lives in a way that is the most meaningful to them. Withholding such information not only prohibits a patient from making fully informed healthcare decisions but it also violates the patient’s rights. In short, there is no way of ever knowing a person’s value scale, or what gives them reason to live the way they choose to. Although it can be argued that disclosure of certain information being given to a patient regarding health could induce anxiety or uncertainty. In the end, it is their right to know about the information because it is a necessary element that is required to make decisions regarding their healthcare. On that note, there are various other situations in life that can produce the same feelings mentioned before, regardless, as humans we tend to take chances with everything we do without ever fully knowing the results until we are faced with them. Autonomy is a fundamental right that allows us to make these decisions for ourselves. Without it, we are powerless to make decisions for
ourselves.
Autonomy is a concept found in moral, political, and bioethical reasoning. Inside these connections, it is the limit of a sound individual to make an educated, unpressured decision. Patient autonomy can conflict with clinician autonomy and, in such a clash of values, it is not obvious which should prevail. (Lantos, Matlock & Wendler, 2011). In order to gain informed consent, a patient
In the realm of medical ethics, there are many topics that are debated and discussed, but there is not necessarily one clear, correct answer. One of these topics is paternalism. Many questions are bandied back and forth: is it beneficial, should it be disallowed entirely, are there instances when paternalism is good and beneficial, and the list goes on. For each of these questions there have been authors who have provided their comments. One such author is Alan Goldman. He draws a very firm line on paternalism, simply put: medical paternalism is deleterious to a patient because it intrudes on their primary rights of liberty and autonomy. This paper is going to expound upon Goldman’s viewpoint in detail, going through point by point how he presents his argument. There will then be a critique of Goldman’s viewpoint that will counter his main points. The counterpoints will show Goldman’s views on paternalism are incorrect and should not be considered valid.
After reading Should Doctors Tell the Truth by Joseph Collins, I started steer away from Collins views. I disagree with Collins thesis because it isn’t permissible to take control of anyone’s autonomy whether or not it’s in his or her best interest.
Wilson , James G. S., “Rights”, Principles of Health Care Ethics, Second Edition, eds. R.E. Ashcroft, A. Dawson, H. Draper and J.R. McMillan. John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. 2007. pp. 239.
In the modern day, health care can be a sensitive subject. Politically, health care in America changes depending on whom is President. Obamacare and Trumpcare are different policies regarding health care, which many people have passionate feelings towards. However, not many Americans are informed about Norman Daniels’ view on health care. Throughout this paper I will be outlining Norman Daniels’ claims on the right to health care, and the fundamental principles in which he derives to construct his argument. By means of evaluating Daniels’ argument, I will then state my beliefs regarding the distributive justice of health care.
Within public health, the issue of paternalism has become a controversial topic. Questions about the ethics of public health are being asked. The role of ethics in medical practice is now receiving close scrutiny, so it is timely that ethical concepts, such as autonomy and paternalism, be re-examined in their applied context (Med J Aust. 1994). Clinically, patients are treated on a one on one basis, but public health’s obligation is toward the protection and promotion of an entire population’s health. So, based on this difference, the gaping questions targeting public health now becomes, under what conditions is it right to intervene and override an individuals’ autonomy? And if so, is the paternalistic intervention justified? Part of the concern
When it comes to a bad diagnosis it is often difficult for doctors to tell their patients this devastating news. The doctor will likely hold back from telling the patient the whole truth about their health because they believe the patient will become depressed. However, Schwartz argues that telling the patient the whole truth about their illness will cause depression and anxiety, but rather telling the patient the whole truth will empower and motivate the patient to make the most of their days. Many doctors will often also prescribe or offer treatment that will likely not help their health, but the doctors do so to make patients feel as though their may be a solution to the problem as they are unaware to the limited number of days they may have left. In comparison, people who are aware there is no cure to their diagnosis and many choose to live their last days not in the hospital or pain free from medications without a treatment holding them back. They can choose to live their last days with their family and will have more time and awareness to handle a will. Schwartz argues the importance of telling patients the truth about their diagnosis and communicating the person’s likely amount of time left as it will affect how the patient chooses to live their limited
... argue. “The world community has deemed individual autonomy to predominate over beneficence in making medical decisions.” (Fogoros) House M.D. delves deep into this conflict with the deceitful patients who withhold vital information from the doctors that could lead to a correct diagnosis. The particular episode “Three Stories” shows this conflict through the lecture with House and the contrasting students. The show conveys the idea that beneficence is more important than autonomy but also realizes that this argument is hard to make and reflects that in its episodes.
Alan Goldman argues that medical paternalism is unjustified except in very rare cases. He states that disregarding patient autonomy, forcing patients to undergo procedures, and withholding important information regarding diagnoses and medical procedures is morally wrong. Goldman argues that it is more important to allow patients to have the ability to make autonomous decisions with their health and what treatment options if any they want to pursue. He argues that medical professionals must respect patient autonomy regardless of the results that may or may not be beneficial to a patient’s health. I will both offer an objection and support Goldman’s argument. I will
In his essay, “The Refutation of Medical Paternalism,” Alan Goldman discusses his argument against differentiation in the roles between physicians and patients. He says the physician may act against a patient’s will in order treat the patient in their best interest. Goldman makes his whole argument around the assumption that a person’s right to decide his or her future is the most important and fundamental right, saying, “the autonomous individual is the source of those other goods he enjoys, and so is not to be sacrificed for the sake of them.” His claim is that most people agree that they are the best judges of their own self-interest and there is an innate value in the freedom to determine their own future. On these principles, Goldman starts by discussing conditions under which paternalism may be justified.
Autonomy is identified as another professional value and one that the nurse must possess. Autonomy is the right to self-determination. Nurse’s respect the patient’s right to make a decision regarding their healthcare. Practical application includes, educating patients and their families on their choices, honoring their right to make their own decision and stay in control of their health, developing care plans in collaboration with the patient (Taylor, C. Lillis, C. LeMone, P. Lynn, P,
Steinbock, Bonnie, Alex J. London, and John D. Arras. "Rule-Utilitarianism versus Act-Utilitarianism." Ethical Issues in Modern Medicine. Contemporary Readings in Bioethics. 8th ed. New York: McGraw-Hill, 2013. 12. Print.
Mid-Term Thesis: Ethical standards in medical research should be universal, not based on the economic circumstances of a region. Agree. A great deal of Ellen Goodman’s fervor and support for her argument comes from an ethical standpoint, a point that comes in conflict with what is argued as the more pragmatic side of the debate on whether the ethical standard of care is a universal right, or if it is adaptable country to country based on need and funding. Ethics and logic are closely intertwined.
The society’s outlook towards healthcare has changed radically over the past three decades. First, there is an increased emphasis on patient autonomy and self-determination or patient-centered medicine whereby patients are the focus of the clinical interaction. The belief that doctors know what is best for patients is fast diminishing. Secondly, there is also growing recognition that improvements in healthcare require collaboration among many different stakeholders, including patients. Thirdly, health is
Healthcare providers must make decisions that would result in the best results for their patients given a particular situation. Currently, there are four ethical principles that rule over the healthcare realm. These four principles are respect for autonomy, nonmaleficence, beneficence and justice. These four ethical principles “tell us what action to take do not take into account the nature of the moral agent” (Gardiner, 297). These four principles disregard emotional responses from its solutions. However, a human being’s nature is closely tied to his/her emotions. Disregarding emotions while making important healthcare decisions may not always bring about the best solution to healthcare problems. Since the healthcare providers are trying to