Wait a second!
More handpicked essays just for you.
More handpicked essays just for you.
Negative impacts of genetic testing
Possible advantage of genetic test
Negative impacts of genetic testing
Don’t take our word for it - see why 10 million students trust us with their essay needs.
In the “Choosing for Disability” by Dena S. Davis, the main thesis is centered on the moral implications of parents purposefully wanting the genetic makeup of their children to reflect their own disability through the use of genetic medicine. I will proceed to summarize the arguments of the thesis in respect to genetic ethics and then critique it on the basis of autonomy. Firstly, Davis analyzes the condition of Deafness and whether it constitutes a disability (harm) or a cultural identity. Davis outlines several viewpoints from the perspective of Deaf advocates who defend the Deaf culture movement. This perspective regards medical interventions, such as the use of cochlear implants and surgical hearing aids, as unethical and detrimental …show more content…
to the Deaf community. Accordingly, Davis mentions that the abortion of Deaf fetuses would be no different than genocide. Since over 90 percent of Deaf children are born to Hearing parents, the implementation of cochlear implants (most likely favored by Hearing parents) would drastically lessen the number of Deaf people in America and thus, annihilating Deaf culture as a whole. Davis lists examples of positive gains from having a Deaf membership ranging from ASL, artistic traditions, cohesive Deaf community with a rich cultural heritage, residential schools, to solidarity that is shared among Deaf people. Many Deaf parents who are interested in bearing children with similar hearing status as themselves say that they would not choose to be Hearing if they were given a chance. Davis also takes into account the opposing viewpoint that considers being Deaf as a harmful condition in need of medical intervention and should be prevented if possible. Despite the perception of Deaf people as non-disabled members of a linguistic and cultural minority, it has been shown that their incomes falls 30 to 40 percent below the national average. Furthermore, Deaf education renders Deaf graduates less academically competent than those in other minority groups and could potentially result in limitations in the workforce. Davis also points out that raising Deaf children using sign language is not as beneficial as it is believed to be, since it requires the parents to learn as well further risking their child “window” for language development and acquisition. In her thesis, Davis deems that there is a moral harm associated with Deafness regardless of it being a culture or a disability. Moral harm is defined as any actions and future decisions that will limit a person’s right to an open future. If Deafness is a culture by standard, then intentionally passing down the inability to hear to children ultimately forces them to take up memberships in the Deaf community, which limit their choices and ability to deviate from the cultural circle. If Deafness is a disability by standard, then intentionally creating a Deaf child is also a moral harm because the inability to hear directly narrows their career choices, life opportunities, and cultural options. Davis regards deliberateness as a crucial component in determining whether it is ethical to produce Deaf children based on the preference of their Deaf parents. In the case of “Deaf of Deaf’ culture where Deaf children are naturally born to Deaf parents (without the use of genetic manipulations), there are no moral or ethical implications in question here because the parents did not intend to give birth to children who are Deaf. According to Davis, intentionally producing children who are unable to hear, regardless of the culture-versus-disability debate, is unethical and constitutes as a moral harm because the choice made by the parents ultimately violates the child’s ability to self-determinate and lead a life free of avoidable restraints. Therefore, any decision and action made preceding birth that hinders a child’s right to an open future is ethically discouraged in respect of the child’s autonomy. As for the parental deliberation over the use of cochlear implant, Davis supports its use stating that parents are morally obligated “to have their children implanted”. Davis ends her thesis with a proposal that “Parents ought not deliberately to substantively constrain the ability of their children to make a wide variety of life choices when they become adults.” Critiques of Davis’ argument can be made in respect to autonomy.
In her argument, the author uses autonomy as the basis for the concept of moral harm. The preservation of autonomy here is specifically for the possible child in that a decision made by the parents is recognized to be a moral harm when it violates the child’s right to liberty and ability to self-determine. In making an argument that defends and preserves a child’s autonomy, Davis does not adequately take into account the autonomy of parents to determine how they choose to bring their own children into the world. It is natural for parents to want their offspring to resemble themselves and Davis severely discredits Deaf parents for deliberately wanting to produce a Deaf child, since Deafness is considered to be a significant harm. Davis’ construction of how Deafness is a significant harm is overwhelmingly unpersuasive and generalized, with overemphasis on Deaf children’s “dismal” reading skills. There are plenty of cases of Deaf individuals successfully earning master and doctorate degrees, occupying a variety of respectable occupations, and doing work within the dominant Hearing social sphere. Being Deaf does not always lead to a lesser reading proficiency, limited employment opportunities, and inabilities to cross cultural boundaries like the causal relationship that Davis is desperately trying to establish. Based on her construction of moral harm, would it also be morally unacceptable for Hearing parents to deliberately wanting to produce a Hearing offspring through the use of genetic manipulations when the child is predisposed to be Deaf? Davis’ stance on moral harms as violations to a person’s right to an open future is biased in that the standard is not equally applicable both ways and tends to be in favor of the Hearing community. In addition, the author’s argument in favor of autonomy for the possible child does not address the “rational persons” aspect of autonomy for cases can made against
the “possible” child for not being of age to meet the standard of rationality to make an informed decision (limited autonomy). Moreover, Davis’ main thesis is build upon a person’s right to an open future as a determining factor, but this criterion requires the knowledge of what is yet to come and happen, so one can never precisely conclude that the life of the possible Deaf child and his future will be diminished and unsatisfactory.
In the autobiography Deaf Again, Mark Drolsbaugh writes about his life being born hearing, growing up hard of hearing, to eventually becoming deaf. By writing this book, he helps many people view from his perspective on what it is like for someone to struggle trying to fit in the hearing society. Through his early years, his eyes were closed to the deaf world, being only taught how to live in a hearing world. Not only does the book cover his personal involvement, but it covers some important moments in deaf history. It really is eye-opening because instead of just learning about deaf culture and deaf history, someone who lived through it is actually explaining their experiences.
In the following chapters, there is an extensive amount of knowledge to learn about how Deaf culture is involved in our modern world. The pages assigned give us an outlook of how Deaf people are treated in our daily life, and how we should learn from it. Its gives a clear line between what are myths and what are facts, to those who are curious about the Deaf community or have specific questions. This book has definitely taught me new things that I could put to good use in the near future. In specific chapters, my mind really opened up to new ideas and made me think hard about questions, like “why don’t some Deaf people trust hearing people,” or “do we need another ‘Deaf president now’ revolution?” I realized many new things in the course of reading this book, and have recommended this to my family.
What I found most interesting about Jarashow’s presentation were the two opposing views: Deaf culture versus medical professionals. Within the Deaf culture, they want to preserve their language and identity. The Deaf community wants to flourish and grow and do not view being deaf as a disability or being wrong. Jarashow stated that the medical field labels Deaf people as having a handicap or being disabled because they cannot hear. Those who are Deaf feel as though medical professionals are trying to eliminate them and relate it to eugenics. It is perceived that those in that field are trying to fix those who are Deaf and eliminate them by making them conform to a hearing world. Those within the Deaf community seem to be unhappy with devices such
In the book Seeing Voices, the author describes the world of the deaf, which he explores with extreme passion. The book begins with the history of deaf people in the United States of America, the horrible ways in which they had been seen and treated, and their continuing struggle to gain hospitality in the hearing world. Seeing Voices also examines the visual language of the deaf, sign language, which is as expressive and as rich as any spoken language. This book covers a variety of topics in deaf studies, which includes sign language, the neurology of deafness, the treatment of Deaf American citizens in history, and the linguistic and social challenges that the deaf community face. In this book, Oliver Sacks does not view the deaf as people having a condition that can be treated, instead he sees the deaf more like a racial group. This book is divided into three parts. In the first part, Oliver Sacks states a strong case for sign language, saying it is in fact a complete language and that it is as comprehensive as English, French, Chinese, and any other spoken language. He also describes the unhappy story of oralism (this is the education of deaf students through oral language by using lip reading, speech, and mimicking the mouth shapes and breathing patterns of speech)) in deaf children’s education. In addition, the first part is about the history of deaf people as well as information about deafness. It also includes the author’s own introduction to the world of the deaf.
Lane, Harlan (1992). “Cochlear Implants are Wrong for Young Deaf Children.” Viewpoints on Deafness. Ed. Mervin D. Garretson. National Association of the Deaf, Silver Spring, MD. 89-92.
...people making decisions for the deaf community. The past resulted in the strengthening of unity in the culture. “They claim the right to “personal diversity”, which is “something to be cherished rather than fixed and erased” (Tucker, 1997).
Throughout the course of the semester, I have gained a new understanding and respect of Deaf culture and the many aspects it encompasses. The information supplied in class through discussion, movies, and guest lecturers since the previous reflection have aided in the enhancement of my knowledge of Deaf culture and nicely wrapped up all of the information provided throughout the semester.
Savulescu, Julian. “Genetic Interventions and the Ethics of Human Beings.” Readings in the Philosophy of Technology. Ed. David Kaplan. 2nd ed. Lanham: Roman & Littlefield, 2009. 417-430.
Tucker, Bonnie. “Deaf Culture, Cochlear Implants, and Elective Disability.” Hastings Center Report. 28.4 (1998): 1-12. Academic Search Complete. EBSCO. Web. 9 Dec. 2013.
Deaf and hearing impaired individuals are know longer an out cast group. They now have there own deaf community. Deaf individuals do not consider themselves having an impairment, handicap, or any type of disability. They believe that through the use of sign language, other communication skills, and technology that there deafness is the way they are supposed to be. Many people who have perfect hearing can not understand deaf people and why they embrace there deafness instead of trying to receive hearing and get rid of there handicap. However not all deaf people have th...
In the United States today, approximately 4500 children are born deaf each year, and numerous other individuals suffer injuries or illnesses that can cause partial or total loss of hearing, making them the largest “disability” segment in the country. Although, those in the medical field focus solely on the medical aspects of hearing loss and deafness, members of the deaf community find this unwarranted focus limiting and restrictive; because of its failure to adequately delineate the sociological aspects and implications of the deaf and their culture. Present day members of deaf culture reject classifications such as “deaf mute” or “deaf and dumb”, as marginalizing them because of their allusions to a presumed disability. (Edwards, 2012, p. 26-30)
The deaf community does not see their hearing impairment as a disability but as a culture which includes a history of discrimination, racial prejudice, and segregation. According to an online transcript,“Through Deaf Eyes” (Weta and Florentine films/Hott productions Inc., 2007) there are thirty-five million Americans that are hard of hearing. Out of the thirty-five million an estimated 300,000 people are completely deaf. There are ninety percent of deaf people who have hearing parents (Halpern, C., 1996). Also, most deaf parents have hearing children. With this being the exemplification, deaf people communicate on a more intimate and significant level with hearing people all their lives. “Deaf people can be found in every ethnic group, every region, and every economic class” (Weta and Florentine films/Hott productions Inc., 2007). The deaf culture and hard of hearing have plenty of arguments and divisions with living in a hearing world without sound however, that absence will be a starting point of an identity within their culture as well as the hearing culture (Weta and Florentine films/Hott productions Inc., 2007).
From a deafness-as-defect mindset, many well-meaning hearing doctors, audiologists, and teachers work passionately to make deaf children speak; to make these children "un-deaf." They try hearing aids, lip-reading, speech coaches, and surgical implants. In the meantime, many deaf children grow out of the crucial language acquisition phase. They become disabled by people who are anxious to make them "normal." Their lack of language, not of hearing, becomes their most severe handicap. While I support any method that works to give a child a richer life, I think a system which focuses on abilities rather than deficiencies is far more valuable. Deaf people have taught me that a lack of hearing need not be disabling. In fact, it shouldn?t be considered a lack at all. As a h...
The evolution of technology has been hand in hand with the human subjugation of earth, but the question persists, when does the use of technology go too far? Advances in medical science have tremendously improved the average human lifespan and the quality of life for individuals. Medical science and biology are steadily arriving at new ways to make humans superior by the use of advanced genetic alteration. This ability raises the question of how ought this new technology be used, if at all? The idea of human enhancement is a very general, since humans are constantly “enhancing” themselves through the use of tools. In referring to human enhancement, I am specifically referring to the use of genetic intervention prior to birth. Julian Savulescu in his, “Genetic Interventions and the Ethics of Enhancement of Human Beings” argues that it is not only permissible to intervene genetically, but is morally obligatory. In this paper I will argue that it is not morally obligatory to genetically intervene, but may be permissible under the criterion established by Savulescu. I plan to argue that the argument used by Savulescu for the obligation to genetically intervene is not the same obligation as the prevention and treatment of disease. The ability for humans to genetically intervene is not sufficient to provide a moral obligation.
This essay will explore the medical model of disability as well as the social model of disability by providing an in depth analysis of the views and explanations that outline each perspective. It will examine and establish the connection of the two models in relation to Deaf people. Furthermore it will illustrate how Deaf people are defined according to each outlook, as well as the issues and concerns that arise from these perceptions. This essay will consider the medical model and the social model to compare the ideas and objectives of the given articles; Caught in the Deaf Trap by Karen Van Rooyen, A Brave New World of Sound by Thandi Skade, Fake Interpreters: A Violation of Human Rights and lastly Professor Graham Turner’s; 10 lessons from the tale of the ‘fake’ interpreter.