Wait a second!
More handpicked essays just for you.
More handpicked essays just for you.
The ethics of animal rights
Introduction to Ethics Quizlet
Ethics philosophy reflection
Don’t take our word for it - see why 10 million students trust us with their essay needs.
In his essay, The Ethics of Respect for Nature, Paul Taylor presents his argument for a deontological, biocentric egalitarian attitude toward nature based on the conviction that all living things possess equal intrinsic value and are worthy of the same moral consideration. Taylor offers four main premises to support his position. (1) Humans are members of the “Earth’s community of life” in the same capacity that nonhuman members are. (2) All species exist as a “complex web of interconnected elements” which are dependent upon one another for their well-being. (3) Individual organisms are “teleological centers of life” which possess a good of their own and a unique way in which to pursue it. (4) The concept that humans are superior to other species is an unsupported anthropocentric bias.
To support his first premise, humans are members of the “Earth’s community of life” in the same capacity that nonhuman members are, Taylor cites the fact that we are only one species among many. Humans are subject to “the [same] laws of genetics, of natural selection, and of adaptation” (p.633) that all other livings
…show more content…
are, thus establishing a common basis for kinship. Taylor also recognizes that we are “relative newcomers” on this planet who are “dependent upon the ecological soundness of many plant and animal communities” but who in turn share no such reliance upon us. Taylor’s second premise, all species exist as a “complex web of interconnected organisms”, is the fundamental concept in ecology and a “biological reality” (p.634) which is empirically supported. He states “the integrity of the entire biosphere…is essential to the realization of the good of its constituent communities, both human and nonhuman”. Essentially, our well-being is dependent upon our relationship with other organisms. His third premise, organisms are “teleological centers of life” which possess a good of their own and a way in which to pursue it, helps Taylor introduce the principles of moral consideration and intrinsic value. He posits that because organisms are goal-directed and strive to preserve themselves and to realize their own good, they have welfare interests. It is possessing the capacity to be benefited or harmed that gives an organism “as a unique irreplaceable individual” (p.635), moral consideration. Because sentience or the ability to feel pain is not a contingency of receiving moral consideration, all living things are worthy of it. In turn the principle of intrinsic value extends to all organisms in the Eath’s community and states that their “good is deserving of concern and consideration”(p.632). In his fourth and perhaps most premise, the claim that humans are superior to other species is unfounded, Taylor cites a number of reasons to accept his position. First, “humans are claiming human superiority from a strictly human point of view”(p.636). We have a inclination to claim our dominance because we possess characteristics other species do not. While this may be true, other species possess traits we do not (the ability to fly, hibernate, regenerate limbs, ect.) which are equally important to their survival as our “human traits” are to ours. Taylor makes the analogy that our evaluation of other species is akin to hierarchical class-structured societies. Instead, he believes the doctrine of species impartiality should be embraced because it engenders an attitude of respect and equality “the biocentric outlook recommends” (p.640). Taylor proposes that his “biocentric outlook on nature” (p.632) is a “philosophical world view” based upon the principles of moral consideration and intrinsic value which apply to each individual organism equally.
He provides us with a virtue ethics approach toward the natural world, how we should act toward other living things must reflect the equal worth each individual possesses. While Taylor admits “such a belief system cannot be proven to be true” it does provide a “coherent, unified, and rationally acceptable picture of a total world” (p.632), and to this end, I believe he was successful. While his species egalitarianism goes against our moral experience, especially as it pertains to nonsentiant beings, it does give us an alternative position to anthropocentrism. The idea that our respect for other species should not be contingent upon their relationship to
us Throughout his argument, we see that Taylor utilizes elements of natural law theory, which states that morally appropriate actions are the ones that follow nature’s directives. The first three premises reflect a belief that all of nature, including mankind, is interrelated and directed toward achieving specific ends that are part of the rational order of life (Vaughn, 2013, p. 71). Taylor also draws from Kantian ethics, extending the scope of the means-end principle to include all living organisms as being creatures of equal intrinsic worth. In turn, our duties to the natural world must reflect the equal status of all, and we can “no longer simply take the human point of view…from the perspective of our own good” (Vaughn, p.630).
In the essay, “Are All Species Equal?” the author, David Schmidtz, stiffly denounces the views on species egalitarianism by philosopher Paul Taylor. Schmidtz explores Taylor’s views from all angles and criticisms and concludes that “biocentrism has a point but that it does not require any commitment to species equality.” (Schmidtz, 115). Schmidtz agrees with the major points of biocentrism; that humans live on the same terms as all other species in the community, that all species are interdependent and are all in pursuit of their own good. However, each species should not all be looked upon as the same and with the same level of contributions as every other species. There’s no way to compare one living thing to another unless the two are exactly identical. Therefore, instead of saying that every species is in fact on the same level, we should respect that each living thing should be evaluated differently. This is where respect for nature comes into play. Respecting each individual species for its own attributions is more just than saying that all should be treated equally. Schmidtz goes on to say that biocentrism and respect for nature do not go hand in hand with species egalitarianism, which to me, is a valid
The long-term aim is to develop an approach to ethics that will help resolve contemporary issues regarding animals and the environment. In their classical formulations and as recently revised by animal and environmental ethicists, mainstream Kantian, utilitarian, and virtue theories have failed adequately to include either animals or the environment, or both. The result has been theoretical fragmentation and intractability, which in turn have contributed, at the practical level, to both public and private indecision, disagreement, and conflict. Immensely important are the practical issues; for instance, at the public level: the biologically unacceptable and perhaps cataclysmic current rate of species extinctions, the development or preservation of the few remaining wilderness areas, the global limitations on the sustainable distribution of the current standard of living in the developed nations, and the nonsustainability and abusiveness of today's technologically intense crop and animal farming. For individuals in their private lives, the choices include, for example: what foods to eat, what clothing to wear, modes of transportation, labor-intensive work and housing, controlling reproduction, and the distribution of basic and luxury goods. What is needed is an ethical approach that will peacefully resolve these and other quandaries, either by producing consensus or by explaining the rational and moral basis for the continuing disagreement.
Our awareness, our perception within nature, as Thomas states, is the contrast that segregates us from our symbols. It is the quality that separates us from our reflections, from the values and expectations that society has oppressed against itself. However, our illusions and hallucinations of nature are merely artifacts of our anthropocentric idealism. Thomas, in “Natural Man,” criticizes society for its flawed value-thinking, advocating how it “[is merely] a part of a system . . . [and] we are, in this view, neither owners nor operators; at best, [are] motile tissues specialized for receiving information” (56). We “spread like a new growth . . . touching and affecting every other kind of life, incorporating ourselves,” destroying the nature we coexist with, “[eutrophizing] the earth” (57). However, Thomas questions if “we are the invaded ones, the subjugated, [the] used?” (57). Due to our anthropocentric idealism, our illusions and hallucinations of nature, we forget that we, as organisms, are microscopically inexistent. To Thomas, “we are not made up, as we had always supposed, of successively enriched packets of our own parts,” but rather “we are shared, rented, occupied [as] the interior of our cells, driving them, providing the oxidative energy that sends us out for the improvement of each shining day, are the mitochondria” (1).
He goes on to describe how this common ancestry means that we still have a lot in common with everything on this planet. Thomas says that "we still share genes around, and the resemblance of the enzymes of grasses to those of whales is a family resemblance" (3). Thomas relates to the reader that he has been trying to conceive of the earth itself as a type of organism, "but it is no go" (4). The earth is just too big, too complex for such an analogy. But then it came to him. The earth is most like a single cell (4).
In “Ideals of Human Excellence and Preserving Natural Environments,” Thomas Hill tries to explain why destroying nature is morally inappropriate. His main argument is that rather than asking whether this action is wrong or right, we should ask what kind of person would destroy nature. Beforehand, one view is that since plants have right or interests, one should not violate their interest by destroying them. But Hill’s view is that we cannot address the interests of plants in order to criticize those who destroy the nature, because this approach is good for sentient beings. In this essay I am going to examine whether sentient is a necessary condition for interests to be counted? My upshot is that Hill’s view is correct.
In the spirit of Karen Warren, Gould's perspective on environmentalism 'feels right' to me, as I can connect with acts of respect and benevolence towards humans and can easily extend that feeling to the rest of the earth (especially on a personal level where I see the golden rule as the basis for my religious beliefs). However, upon closer examination, I find the suggestion to 'just follow the golden rule' as an environmental ethic problematic when examined in a practical, non-idealized light. Harkening back to the problems encountered in previous discussions of biocentric and ecocentric ethics, I am troubled by the potential outcomes of an environmental ethic such as this.
Perhaps the most important question moral philosophy can ask is: who or what is entitled to moral rights? When we discuss differing moral philosophies such as utilitarianism or deontology we do so with the underlying assumption that human beings are centric to the moral code. Should we assume this? Historically speaking humans have only been present on this planet for 100,000 years. The planet itself has been around 4.6 billion years, so the environment and animal life existed long before intelligent human life emerged. Why then, is morality generally accepted to be applied solely to humans? To answer this question I intend to discuss some of the basic tenets of morality, such as the moral community. What does membership in the moral community entail? Does not being a contributing member to the moral community mean that you are not entitled to moral consideration? The way humans deal with the topics of animal rights and environmentalism hinge upon the answer to these questions.
The book gives us the vision that we have a way now to change other species and even our destiny. Everyone should be aware of this new-found ability and they should be aware of its ups and downs. It is hard to define what is natural today. Organisms have always influenced each other in subtle and significant ways. The difference is the artificial selection; human came in and added unnatural tools with human purpose and desire.
Most would agree with Taylor’s first two elements of the biocentric outlook on nature. The first element it is undeniably true; humans are indeed members of Earth’s community. Taylor pushes this further and asserts that humans are non-privileged members of the earth’s community of life. Humans, just like all other living organisms, have biological requirements to live. Moreover, “[w]e, as they, are vulnerable. We share with them an inability to guarantee the f...
After a thorough close reading of this novel “Creation” I have asked myself a lot of question. First of all when I took a look at the quote book “Is there an “earthborn, yet transcendental obligation we are both morally bound to share” we all have a role to play in the conservation
We change the power on the microscope to look at Rollin's argument for a sentientist approach. With this view, the moral category includes all sentient beings, not just human beings. Rollins believes that any being possessing an awareness of the senses that does not involve thought or perception has intrinsic value and is an end-in-themselves. He contends that animal interests must also be considered when determining our environmental oblig...
In this essay, I will discuss and define both speciesism and moral individualism in Paola Cavalieri’s book, The Animal Question. Additionally, I will provide my opinion on which is the strongest argument for speciesism and why I still disagree with it. Speciesism is the belief that humans are inherently superior to all other animals, solely based on their species membership. This widely held belief is used to justify the blatant discrimination of nonhuman animals, resulting in a lack of moral rights and the exploitation of defenseless beings. This view, that humans are of special moral status, is constantly attempted to be rationalized in various ways.
(i) Plumwood tries to provide a rational for environmentalism by saying that nature, in her experience with the crocodile, provides “a humbling and cautionary tale about our relationship with the earth, about the need to acknowledge our own animality and ecological vulnerability” (Plumwood, p. 271). Maintaining an ecosystem’s integrity is important because it entails the preservation and respect of animals that may prey upon us (acknowledging our ecological vulnerability), which acts as a test for the strength of our identity of being just another animal on the earth (acknowledging our animality). She says that maintaining the environment is important because it humbles and reminds us of our place in the world—we are not above the rest of the animals, and we must be conscientiousness of the inaccuracy of our own internal narrative, which provides this illusion (Plumwood, p.
Though Blackstone created these thoughts well over 200 years ago, they are more relevant now than ever before. He reasoned that “changing environmental conditions” require us to restrict traditional freedoms and property rights in the name of public welfare and equality (Desjardins, 104). Due to dwindling natural resources and rising concerns of pollution, those previous rights and freedoms can no longer exist if the welfare of posterity is to be protected. To say that millions of unborn humans have a right to anything, even before existing in our world, is an odd concept. However, this sentiment conveys perhaps the single most compelling argument for why an anthropocentric approach to environmental ethics is in fact, the most justified. It is the instinct of all living beings to prioritize oneself and ensure a future for those to come (Acari, 2017). Though this justification for protecting the natural world might seem selfish or short-sighted, it is in fact, the nature of all life to preserve self-interests. In response to the counterclaim that plants and animals should be regarded with natural rights like humans, Blackstone would rebut that these beings are incapable of “free and rational thought” (Desjardins, 103). This is most likely in part due to his purely anthropocentric perspective that human life alone is worth consideration. Thus,
It would be desirable to live one’s life, having a reverential stance on all forms of life. This is because we all inhabit the same area, relatively speaking, and life forms are frail and often break and are destroyed. Living like this is desirable, as it would mean, that the life that we often have control or influence over wouldn’t be taken for granted. When we look at how nature in different parts of the world are treated, such as clear cutting forests that dramatically damage not only the inhabitants of the biosphere, but also cause vulnerabilities to the land itself such as increased landslides, and more. Although an example, the idea behind it could be extended further, in reverence for all life, and that without