Wait a second!
More handpicked essays just for you.
More handpicked essays just for you.
Essays on justice in plato republic
Plato and Aristotle on justice
Essays on justice in plato republic
Don’t take our word for it - see why 10 million students trust us with their essay needs.
Recommended: Essays on justice in plato republic
The idea of justice is one that generally most people will agree on but almost no one can explain why. In The Republic by Plato, Socrates tries to come up with a way to find true justice. After making his argument, it is inferred that Plato takes over the argument, but continues to use Socrates as a mouthpiece. To help in understanding an analogy is created and although it seems reasonable at first, it is not. Plato tries his best to have his line of reasoning flawless, nonetheless it has flaws. His ideology along with his analogy are flawed, which consecutively means that justice is not how he makes it out to be. Justice comes into play in a conversation between Cephalus, an older man who is an archetype of Athens at the time, and Socrates, …show more content…
With no way to argue with that,Cephalus quickly dismisses himself and hands his argument down to his son, Polemarchus. Polemarchus does not argue any better than his father and simply states that justice is harming your enemies and benefitting your friends. Socrates does not accept this statement and questions Polemarchus on how he would be able to tell whether a friend is genuine or not. An upset Thrasymachus then steps in and says that justice is whatever will be advantageous to the stronger, meaning that justice is decided by those in power, and that justice is not beneficial except for reputation. Through a long discussion, Socrates is able to use analogies,logic, and questioning to prove to Thrasymachus that it is not profitable and that acting justly will have better results than acting unjustly. Thrasymachus abandons the conversation and Glaucon, who is not fully convinced of Socrates’ argument, …show more content…
To start off, Plato’s city has holes and he also did not consider any other aspect other than what would be ideal for him. It is understandable that it is his ideology so whether it transfers well to the real world does not matter but there are parts that do not match up. The most obvious one would be that once he sets up his city he tries to track it back to the just individual it does noted up. Within the individual it is explained that their soul has three parts, such like his caste system. Iron within the individual is appetite which he states cannot be satisfied. Silver is spirit which he associated with revenge. Gold is reason which would be the mediator between appetite and revenge. Clearly it does not connect well that iron within the city is moderate but within the individual is unsatisfiable granting that his city would not work. Socrates would not identify this as a just city if the logic behind it does not make sense and has holes. His entire existence is based off questioning and trying to find truth and truth is meant to be complete. Along with that, if Plato did censor forms of art it would certainly not fly well with Socrates, the reason being that he is trying to find truth. On a biographical point, Socrates would be part of the lower/iron class and having his fate decided for him would not be
...purpose is “to unmask the hypocrisy and show how the meaning of Justice is being perverted” . He is not prepared to argue, leaving Socrates victorious. Here, Socrates’s method of argumentative questioning is insufficient and naïve against a stubborn, powerful and philosophically certain moral skeptic. This is confirmed by the change in investigative approach in the latter books. Thus the ‘earlier’ Plato cannot adequately respond to Thrasymachus’s immoralist view of Justice.
Philosophers, like Socrates, question why things are, how they should be and what the best way to live is. Philosophy can be disturbing, as it was with Cephalus because it may contradict what you previously believed in. In this particular conversation with Cephalus, he asks, "What is justice?" There are many answers to this question, and Cephalus provides the simple definition that justice is telling the truth and paying one's debts.
Thrasymachus has just stated, "Justice is nothing other than the advantage of the stronger", and is now, at the request of Socrates, clarifying his statement.
Socrates reaches a conclusion that defies a common-sense understanding of justice. Nothing about his death sentence “seems” just, but after further consideration, we find that his escape would be as fruitless as his death, and that in some sense, Socrates owes his obedience to whatever orders Athens gives him since he has benefited from his citizenship.
Plato’s Republic focuses on one particular question: is it better to be just or unjust? Thrasymachus introduces this question in book I by suggesting that justice is established as an advantage to the stronger, who may act unjustly, so that the weak will “act justly” by serving in their interests. Therefore, he claims that justice is “stronger, freer, and more masterly than justice” (Plato, Republic 344c). Plato begins to argue that injustice is never more profitable to a person than justice and Thrasymachus withdraws from the argument, granting Plato’s response. Glaucon, however, is not satisfied and proposes a challenge to Plato to prove that justice is intrinsically valuable and that living a just life is always superior. This paper will explain Glaucon’s challenge to Plato regarding the value of justice, followed by Plato’s response in which he argues that his theory of justice, explained by three parts of the soul, proves the intrinsic value of justice and that a just life is preeminent. Finally, it will be shown that Plato’s response succeeds in answering Glaucon’s challenge.
To conclude, Socrates’ idea of justice is an excellence of the soul and produces no harms, leading to a more profitable life and is valued for itself and its results (357c). Although Socrates’ view of justice was greatly challenged by Glaucon claims about justice, his view could be defended through examining his many arguments, analogies and revelations about justice.
Truth be told there is no real justice in Socrates? ?just city?. Servitude of those within his city is crucial to its function. His citizens are, in every aspect, slaves to the functionality of a city that is not truly their own. True justice can not be achieved through slavery and servitude, that which appears to be justice (and all for the sake of appearances) is all that is achieved. Within Socrates? city there is no room for identity, individuality, equality, or freedom, which are the foundations justice was built upon. These foundations are upheld within a proper democracy. In fact, the closest one can experience justice, on a political level, is through democracy.
The debate between Thrasymachus and Socrates begins when Thrasymachus gives his definition of justice in a very self-interested form. Thrasymachus believes that justice is only present to benefit the ruler, or the one in charge – and for that matter any one in charge can change the meaning of justice to accommodate their needs (343c). Thrasymachus provides a very complex example supporting his claim. He states that the man that is willing to cheat and be unjust to achieve success will be by far the best, and be better than the just man.
Out of the confrontation with Cephalus, Polemarchus, and Thrasymachus, Socrates emerges as a reflective individual searching for the rational foundation of morality and human excellence. The views presented by the three men are invalid and limited as they present a biased understanding of justice and require a re-examination of the terminology. The nature in which the faulty arguments are presented, leave the reader longing to search for the rational foundations of morality and human virtue.
Throughout all of history, a just man has been considered an individual who lives a life of excellence. However, as time has progressed, so has the definition of a “life of excellence” itself. Thus, an individual who was considered just in the 5th century BCE would possess very different characteristics than a just man today, despite the fact that both were considered to be men who achieved areté: the life of excellence.
In his philosophical text, The Republic, Plato argues that justice can only be realized by the moderation of the soul, which he claims reflects as the moderation of the city. He engages in a debate, via the persona of Socrates, with Ademantus and Gaucon on the benefit, or lack thereof, for the man who leads a just life. I shall argue that this analogy reflecting the governing of forces in the soul and in city serves as a sufficient device in proving that justice is beneficial to those who believe in, and practice it. I shall further argue that Plato establishes that the metaphorical bridge between the city and soul analogy and reality is the leader, and that in the city governed by justice the philosopher is king.
Plato's Republic uses dialogue between Socrates and fellow Athenians in order to tease out the complexities of the idea of justice. In Book II, the question of the value of justice is raised, through the dialogue between Glaucon, his brother Adeimantus, and Socrates. Socrates is challenged by the brothers to refute their view on justice, and to explain whether justice is good in and of itself or only for its results. Socrates fails to completely refute Glaucon and Adeimantus' view, by failing to answer one argument and relying on an incorrect premise for another.
He uses the traditional definition of a just life—paying what one owes to gods and men, and being honest. Socrates dismisses this definition and uses this example: if a person receives a weapon from a friend who then becomes insane, would it be just to return that weapon if the friend asked for it back? In this case, what would be justice - giving him his weapon back or not? The two men then agree that telling the truth and returning what you receive cannot be the definition of justice. Because Cephalus's definition fails he goes to prepare the sacrifice for the festival, and Polemarchus continues the
...is own desires rather than his subjects needs is not virtuous. Second, a person in the military, who is supposed to be courageous may desert his fellow troops in fear. Third, many common people commit crimes, and create conflict within the community. None of these people are virtuous. However, this is exactly what Plato was getting at. Plato believes that when each of these classes performs its own role and does not try to take over any other class, the entire city as a whole will operate smoothly, showing the harmony that is genuine justice. (ln 433e) What makes the Republic such an important and interesting piece of literature is that by examining what brings true justice and harmony to the world, we can therefore understand all of the virtues by considering how each is placed within the organization of an ideal city.
For Plato’s thesis – justice pays – to be validated, he has to prove two things, the first being that justice is inherently good. In