Wait a second!
More handpicked essays just for you.
More handpicked essays just for you.
Hegel phenomenology of spirit, independence and dependence of self-consciousness: lordship and bondage
Hegel phenomenology of spirit, independence and dependence of self-consciousness: lordship and bondage
Critique of Hegel's phenomenology of spirit
Don’t take our word for it - see why 10 million students trust us with their essay needs.
Recommended: Hegel phenomenology of spirit, independence and dependence of self-consciousness: lordship and bondage
Social scientists often reference Georg Hegel’s work in Phenomenology of Spirit, as he attempts to develop the notion of self and the limits of its autonomy in society. In it, he describes what is often termed the master-slave dialectic. The master-slave dialectic describes the internal, or if taken more literally, the external struggle of recognition between two figures, the master and the slave. Their relationship is at once both reflective and reflexive, as one begins to understand the other as the antithesis of his or herself, giving an identity not only to the other, but also to his or herself. This dialectic places the figures in conflict with one another, where the historically determined means for resolution is the social defeat of …show more content…
one figure. That figure now assumes the position in the world as the slave, while the other, maintains his liberty as the master. In America in World Civilizations, we have thus far covered the migration and colonization of European powers into the New World across the Atlantic, the Americas. While all explorers ventured to the Americas with the common goal of national expansion, their motivations regarding this expansion were varied. From social and religious, to political and economical, the different forces that drove the European exploration dictated the nature of the interactions the settlers had with the native American Indians. In much the same way that Hegel points to the inevitable contention between two consciousnesses within society, there are several observed instances of unfreedom and domination between Europeans, Indians, and Africans. Though Hegel describes such interactions between a master and slave as codependent, they are also, in a sense, immutable states. In the cases of Álvar Núñez Cabeza de Vaca, Pocahontas, and Olaudah Equiano, for example, their positions in society superficially shift from freedom to unfreedom and seem to challenge this dialectic. However, it is clear in the narratives of their lives that they do not ever overcome this unfreedom because they were never free; all three characters were always in a state of subjugation. To allude to Aristotle’s, another philosopher’s, arguments about the naturalness of slavery, he states: “Now nature has distinguished between the female and the slave […] But among barbarians no distinction is made between women and slaves […].” Barbaric societies, like what many European writers labeled Indian culture in the Americas, according to Aristotle, regarded women in the same plane as they regarded slaves. They were tools, extensions of men that were utilized to advance the agendas of both individual men (ie: father or husband) or a collective of men (ie: soldiers, chiefs). For Pocahontas, this was her function within her society. In the Camilla Townsend text, Pocahontas and the Powhatan Dilemma, there is a vivid description of the various levels of unfreedom that the young Pocahontas faced in her life, both egregious and subtle. Even within the title of the book, it situates Pocahontas in the forefront of a dilemma of men (the plight of Powhatan, her father, and Powhatan people, her patriarchal tribesmen). Such juxtaposition is allusive to the Pocahontas’ role throughout the entire text. The young Pocahontas is described as a mediator, a sort of ambassador for her father and her people, travelling to and fro opposing Indian tribes as well as English settlements. Was this asserting the power and independence of Pocahontas? While certainly, this may deviate from the normative view of servitude, Townsend suggests that Pocahontas merely engaged these men, delivering messages and beginning dialogue between rival factions, yet herself never seemed to gain the respect or acknowledgement of having any power to do so: “But the master, the husband, and the king are not in the habit of pondering the thoughts and feelings of those beneath them. So, too, the English colonizers gazed at Pocahontas and judged her, but did not ask her what she thought.” If this was the status of Pocahontas while she was physically free, it is not difficult to comprehend how her kidnap and enslavement by the Patawomeck tribe only further solidified her un-free position in society. Her kidnap held value for the English and other Indians not because Pocahontas herself was intrinsically important, but because she symbolized the power and authority of both her father and her tribe. This sentiment is echoed even when Pocahontas is assimilated into English culture in the Old World. Upon her marriage to John Rolfe and return to his homeland, Townsend details how, “[…] the British were fascinated by her, adored her exoticism.“ Pocahontas’ life and legacy were marred by her objectification and domination as a mere slave and instrument of male agenda. Similarly, Olaudah Equiano, the Eboe African who was kidnapped from what is now modern day Nigeria, and brought to various places throughout Africa, the Americas, and Europe, was no more than a bondsman to the many people he served and travelled with in his journeys.
In his autobiography, The Interesting Narrative of the Life of Olaudah Equiano, he begins with a detailed description of life in his homeland. He describes a culture that had a hierarchal, patriarchal system, not unlike that of Pocahontas’ tribe. There is an established government, with chiefs and judges, one of which, is his father. It is important to note that while Equiano states that he was slated to claim the status of “grandeur”, he never reached that point in his narrative before he was kidnapped and sold as but another slave in the Middle Passage. Thus, early life for Equiano, while perhaps better than some of his counterparts, was still of the same class, dictated by the governance of these socially superior figures. Similar to Pocahontas too, Equiano eventually regained a “free” status. But unlike Pocahontas who is still bound by the voyeuristic gaze of the men surrounding her, Equiano’s unfreedom stems from the social stigma and struggle of being non-white European. As he recounted during his time in the Barbados, “as I knew there was little or no law for a free negro here […].” The social intolerance of African people, while different in the Caribbean from in England or America, was still clear. …show more content…
Equiano’s time in England was by far more favorable than the conditions he endured on American or Caribbean soil, yet he notes, “Soon after my arrival in London, I saw a remarkable circumstance relative to African complexion, which I thought so extraordinary, that I beg leave just to mention it […].” In the same way, that Pocahontas never fully escapes the bounds of slavery, Equiano too, regardless of his technical status as a free or not, never avoids subordination by whites in any setting. Lastly, Cabeza de Vaca’s account too, illustrates the transformative nature of unfreedom. Cabeza de Vaca’s upbringing is unique from that of Pocahontas and Equiano in that he enjoyed a relatively privileged upbringing. Alvár Núñez Cabeza de Vaca was born into a hidalgo (Spanish nobility) family, which enabled him the opportunity to travel to America, in 1527, with Pánfilo de Narváez’s expedition to the Florida Gulf Coast. In Andrés Reséndez’s text, A Land So Strange: The Epic Journey of Cabeza de Vaca, he provides little detail into the early life of Cabeza de Vaca, making it difficult to derive any form of unfreedom from that period. The book instead focuses on the events leading up to and during the voyage, which provides a few examples of the servitude-like inferiority that Cabeza de Vaca faces as an adult. The first instance is his role within the expedition. Though Cabeza de Vaca was considered one of the officers of the crew, he still ranked below several crewmembers such as fellow castaways, Castillo and Dorantes, and obviously below the Governor, Narváez. In fact, Reséndez points to a particular moment where, “[Narváez] also saw an opportunity to shame his Royal Treasurer in public.” Narváez was not reticent about asserting his authority over his men, especially, the oft-dissenting Cabeza de Vaca. As aforementioned, the transition from corporeal autonomy to bondage only served to aggravate the severity of unfreedom for individuals. For Cabeza de Vaca, his capture and enslavement by different Indian tribes was revelatory; he eventually understood the extent of his unfreedom within this new society. Reséndez compares this unfreedom that Cabeza de Vaca experiences to the unfreedom that women like Pocahontas endured, where the men demanded grueling amounts of labor production from the women, yet the women enjoyed none of the social or economic prosperity that one might think would result from their work. He also compares Cabeza de Vaca’s (and that of his fellow Spaniards’) unfreedom to that of the African slave, Estebanico, noting, “[…] the fact that the white Europeans were also enslaved must have reduced the disparities. Indians, not Spaniards, exercised the ultimate authority now […] Estebanico became just another slave largely undistinguishable from his former masters.” This allusion to the endeavors of African slaves continues, as Cabeza de Vaca found himself in a quandary between ostensible freedom and apparent unfreedom when he is given the title of shaman. Though his exalted status was definitely better than absolute slavery, it can be interpreted through the text that their “powers” were nothing short of exploited by various Indian groups. Whatever intellectual or spiritual knowledge the castaways provided was gratefully taken for as long as it could be provided, while making clear that, “Although the outsiders appeared to lead the procession, real power remained in the hands of Indian lords who chose to stay in the background.” What would have become of Cabeza de Vaca and his companions if their medical rituals had failed seems to point to imminent regression into marked inferiority and slavery. Though the background and accounts of the lives of Pocahontas, Olaudah Equiano, and Alvár Núñez Cabeza de Vaca are drastically different, they are interconnected by their shared experience in unfreedom.
Though to some extent all three may have seemingly lived, for a brief period of time, individualistically, they are still bound to the social, cultural, familial, and political restraints that mitigate their supposed independence. As Hegel suggests in his master-slave dialectic, all people are subjected to this greater social machine, a static dichotomy. Therefore, their tangible enslavement is not a break from their own sovereignty, but rather is an awakening and acceptance to the pervasive unfreedom and social defeat they have always
faced.
Document One The Journey to Slavery is about the life of Olaudah Equiano. Equiano was born in what is now Nigeria in 1745. At the age of 11 Equiano and his younger sister were taken from their home, drug though the woods, sold, and was then separated from one another. Equiano’s experience was considered very rare. Throughout his life as a slave he had three different owners. Equiano went from one master to the other till he ended up in a pleasant country in the hands of a leader with children and two wives. He describes how his owners treated him like he was part of the family. They spoke he same
The fight for racial equality is one of the most prominent issues Americans have faced throughout history and even today; as the idea that enslaving individuals is unethical emerged, many great and innovative authors began writing about the issues that enslaved people had to face. Olaudah Equiano was no exception. In his work The Interesting Narrative of the Life of Olaudah Equiano, he attempts to persuade his readers that the American way of slavery is brutal, inhumane, and unscrupulous. Equiano manages to do this by minimizing the apparent differences between himself and his primarily white audience, mentioning the cruelties that he and many other slaves had to face, and the advantages of treating your slaves correctly.
In comparison to other slaves that are discussed over time, Olaudah Equiano truly does lead an ‘interesting’ life. While his time as a slave was very poor there are certainly other slaves that he mentions that received far more damaging treatment than he did. In turn this inspires him to fight for the abolishment of slavery. By pointing out both negative and positive events that occurred, the treatment he received from all of his masters, the impact that religion had on his life and how abolishing slavery could benefit the future of everyone as a whole; Equiano develops a compelling argument that does help aid the battle against slavery. For Olaudah Equiano’s life journey expressed an array of cruelties that came with living the life of an
To Hegel, the history of the developing self-conscious mind was the same as the history of philosophy. Through out time, conflicting theories have laid claim to their one exclusive form of truth. Hegel implies that we should not focus on these conflicted ideals but view each as “elements of an organic unity”. This places Hegel as part of a progression of philosophers (Plato, Aristotle, and Kant) who can generally by described as Idealists, whom regarded freedom or self-determination as real and being important for the soul or mind or divinity.
To scrutinize Hegel is simply impossible without attending to his dialectical method resulting in Aufhebung of the oppositions. In the present context this attention should have political and ethical twist - to extract from Hegel's dialectical play some points that are relevant even nowadays (both in political and philosophical terms).
Hegel, although still holds the blemish of a Absolute State's thinker, not democratic, in his work, mainly in what refers to the "Philosophy of the Right", makes possibles the deepening of the investigations for authors like Rawls, who worries about questi...
According to Hegel, “the self conscious is itself and for itself” meaning that it has to come outside of itself, so that it can do two things. One is to cancel out the other otherness. The second is to try to become recognized. This recognition process is called Master and Servant self-conscious. The conflict between master and servant is one in which the historical themes such as dependence and independence are introduced. It sets up the realization of the self conscious through the recognition of and by another, through mutual recognition.
Marx, as previously mentioned, seem similar in many ways to Hegel. However Marx addressed rights in a more helpful manner for us, than Hegel did. Whereas Hegel said it presented the self as `atomistic`, Marx worked with it directly and fitted it neatly within his thought. Rights, (and by rights he was addressing A) according to Marx is constructed by the owners of the means of production for their benefit. This makes it rather simple to conclude if A is indeed equal to B according to Marx, as long as one can simply justify this statement by Marx. “Good” to Marx have clear resonance from Hegel, and in order to explain what good is I will briefly complete, as Marx did, the framework which we started with Hegel. Marx used the parts of Hegel’s work in which he meant Hegel was true to himself.
In The Phenomenology of Spirit Hegel dives deep into his most sought ought ideology of the master-slave dialectic, which describes the process self-consciousness and need for recognition. This ideology played a particular role in Frantz Fanon’s novel Black Skins White Masks in one of the ending chapters in his critique of Western colonialism. Taking a look into Hegel’s master-slave dialectic and understanding the impact that it had in Fanons relationship to colonial context will provide a differing view of the master-slave dialectic relationship.
Hegel’s myth, or “Master-slave dialectic” notions that the fear of losing one’s identity results in a domination over another. This occurs when a being feels the need to be firmly secure within a societal position. In our group we agreed, riots or protest today occur when one obtains an unwanted societal position deemed by another class, or “master.”
Hegel is considered one of the most famous German philosopher’s who wrote and taught during the early 1800’s. Hegel thought that humanity and civilizations was inevitable working towards becoming a free society in hope that this idea and process would spread throughout the world. Many of Hegel’s ideas such as his dialect and triad greatly influenced the 19th century. This movement also translated over into the ideas and findings of people in the new world with liberal and free market democracies who represent the final state of Hegel’s progress. Hegel’s ideas can all be seen as part of a progression and broken down and explained through his teachings and theories, the Hegelian triad, and the legacy that Hegel left behind.
In his Introduction to the Philosophy of History Hegel confronts the reader with a new way of understanding history. According to this infamous philosopher, there are three methods of dealing with history: original, reflective, and philosophic. The approach taken by Hegel is the philosophical approach to history, which is the foundation of his work. In order to understand this approach, Hegel introduces the reader to his understanding of what history is.
The highest level of awareness of consciousness is what is referred as Absolute, in Hegel’s ‘Phenomenology of Spirit’. The phrase might be an adequate hint for the intention behind the title of the article. Nonetheless, my interest in the article will still be to illustrate why Hegel has said that the Absolute is essentially a result.
Hegel's claim that self-consciousness realizes itself in ethical life is set up with the understanding that un-reactive immersion in the social community is no longer possible for modern human beings in his own time. In Hegel's view, ethical life is created within the culture and practices of the social community of an individual. “Ethical life is a system of norms and mores belonging to a social body, made up of spheres of social interaction and interdependence in which all individuals are embedded.” (Philosophy of Right, III: Ethical Life.) More importantly, the individual must follow that ethical life, and therefore contribute to the society himself. Ethical life is a stage of self consciousness towards which the individual of Hegel’s time is seen by Hegel to be living within, and to be constructing throughout his life. Hegel would claim that the moral individual would not try to dissociate from this, for his own benefit. He argues that reason is manifested in the benefit of the individual rather than of the social.
If Hegel considered the absolute idea as the outcoming principle or substantial base of being, then a new phenomenology of spirit must be abstracted from the question stated of the primary and secondary character of the material and ideal in a global plan. But this conception of the materialistic philosophy should be over comprehended, where spiritual is considered as the secondary phenomenon, so as the secondary in comparison with the material side of being. This new phenomenology of the spirit is based on the Hegelian and Marxist traditions’ overcomprehension of the main idea, which takes up the subjective content and spiritual material base — its material-ideal nature. Both a society and an individual possess such qualities and properties that cannot be understood only through the conventional ideology of objective, material being. There exist spiritual phenomena as well, understood here as everything linked to consciousness, psychology, feelings, perception, etc.