Example Of Ambiguity In Color Perceptions By Ewald Hering

902 Words2 Pages

Certain perceptual phenomena such as color afterimages cannot be explained by the trichromatic theory. Ewald Hering proposed in the late 19th century the opponent process theory, stating that some color combinations such as reddish-green or yellowish-blue cannot be seen by humans (Hurvich, & Jameson, 1960). Opponent-process theory suggests that color perception is controlled by three opponent systems; a blue-yellow, a red-green, and black-white mechanism. This is mediated by a process of excitatory and inhibitory responses, with the components of each mechanism opposing each other. Opponent theory can explain phenomena such as negative afterimages, where photoreceptors are overstimulated to a specific color and lose sensitivity to it. Staring …show more content…

Metamerism refers to the phenomenon where the colors of objects with different physical properties (i.e. surfaces with different luminance spectra) are perceived exactly the same by the human eye. Such colors are called metamers (Foster, Amano, Nascimento, & Foster, 2006). Metamers are created since any possible combination of the output of the 3 cone types can be recreated by different luminance spectra. Illuminant metameric failure means that objects that appear to have matching colors under certain lighting conditions can also appear to be different in color under different lighting conditions. Such mismatch has important industrial ramifications since the color of products produced under the manufacturing lights might not match the color where they are sold (Wyszecki, & Stiles, 1982). The visual ambiguity introduced by illuminant metameric failure is contradicted by color constancy. Color constancy refers to the perception that an object’s apparent color remains relatively stable under different illuminants (Brainard, 2004). A banana is perceived as yellow whether viewed under bright sunlight, or under fluorescent kitchen light, or even under dim …show more content…

Color constancy is of great biological value since it allows the adaptation across differing scenes and the identification of objects under different lighting conditions (Faruq, McOwan, & Chittka, 2013). A study by Jin and Shevell (1996) examined color constancy in relation to color memory hypotheses. Their results support the surface-reflectance hypothesis which states that the color recalled from memory depends on the spectral reflectance properties of the object but not on the spectral power distribution of the illuminant. Other studies focused on the neural mechanisms behind color constancy, identifying 3 major such mechanisms: cone adaptation, spatial comparisons of cone and cone-opponent signals, and invariant cell responses (Foster, 2011). It is worth noting that a number of studies have found color constancy either to be imperfect or that the experimental results varied so much, that constancy does not exist (Foster, 2003). Despite the fact that illuminant metameric failure clearly contradicts color constancy, and that the mechanisms mediating color constancy still remain unclear, the general consensus is that such results cannot be used as an argument against color constancy (Logvinenko, Funt, Mirzaei, & Tokunaga,

Open Document